Page 68 - Cultural Theory and Popular Culture an Introduction
P. 68

CULT_C03.qxd  10/24/08  17:12  Page 52







                 52   Chapter 3 Culturalism

                      ‘Nobody is in any way a better person morally or in any other way for liking Beethoven
                      more than Adam Faith. . . . Of course the person who likes both is in a very happy posi-
                      tion since he is able to enjoy much more in his life than a lot of other people’ (ibid.:
                      27). Although Hall and Whannel (1964) recognize ‘the honest intention’ in Arnold’s
                      remarks, they question what they call ‘the random use of Adam Faith as an example’
                      because, as they claim, ‘as a singer of popular songs he is by any serious standards far
                      down the list’. Moreover, as they explain, ‘By serious standards we mean those that
                      might be legitimately applied to popular music – the standards set, for example, by
                      Frank Sinatra or Ray Charles’ (28). What Hall and Whannel are doing here is rejecting
                      the arguments of both Leavisism, and the (mostly American) mass culture critique,
                      which claims that all high culture is good and that all popular culture is bad, for an
                      argument which says, on the one hand, that most high culture is good, and on the
                      other, contrary to Leavisism and the mass culture critique, that some popular culture is
                      also good – it is ultimately a question of popular discrimination.
                         Part of the aim of The Popular Arts,then, is to replace the ‘misleading generalizations’
                      of earlier attacks on popular culture by helping to facilitate popular discrimination
                      within and across the range of popular culture itself. Instead of worrying about the
                      ‘effects’ of popular culture, ‘we should be seeking to train a more demanding audience’
                      (35). A more demanding audience, according to Hall and Whannel, is one that prefers
                      jazz to pop, Miles Davis to Liberace, Frank Sinatra to Adam Faith, Polish films to main-
                      stream Hollywood, L’Année Dernière à Marienbad to South Pacific;and knows intuitively
                      and instinctively that high culture (‘Shakespeare, Dickens and Lawrence’) is usually
                      always best. They take from Clement Greenberg (who took it from Theodor Adorno)
                      the idea that mass culture is always ‘pre-digested’ (our responses are predetermined
                      rather than the result of a genuine interaction with the text or practice), and use the
                      idea as a means to discriminate, not just between good and bad popular culture, but
                      to suggest that it can also be applied to examples of high culture: ‘The important point
                      about such a definition [culture as “pre-digested”] is that it cuts across the commonplace
                      distinctions. It applies to films but not all, to some TV but not all. It covers segments
                      of the traditional as well as the popular culture’ (36).
                         Their approach leads them to reject two common teaching strategies often encoun-
                      tered when popular culture is introduced into the classroom. First, there is the defens-
                      ive  strategy  that  introduces  popular  culture  in  order  to  condemn  it  as  second-rate
                      culture. Second, the ‘opportunist’ strategy that embraces the popular tastes of students
                      in the hope of eventually leading them to better things. ‘In neither case’, they contend,
                      ‘is there a genuine response, nor any basis for real judgements’ (37). Neither would
                      lead to what they insist is necessary: ‘a training in discrimination’ (ibid.). This is not
                      (to repeat a point made earlier) the classic discrimination of Leavisism, defending the
                      ‘good’ high culture against the encroachments of the ‘bad’ popular culture, but dis-
                      crimination within popular culture: the necessity to discriminate within and not just
                      against popular culture; sifting the good popular culture from the bad popular culture.
                      However, although they do not believe in introducing the texts and practices of popu-
                      lar  culture  into  education  ‘as  steppingstones  in  a  hierarchy  of  taste’  leading  ultim-
                                       9
                      ately to real culture, they do still insist (as do Hoggart and Williams) that there is a
   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73