Page 21 - Foundations of Cognitive Psychology : Core Readings
P. 21

Visual Awareness  17

               and with the computer, Turing asserted that the computer should be judged
               ‘‘intelligent.’’ It would then be said to have ‘‘passed Turing’s test.’’
                 Note that Turing’s test is a strictly behavioral test because the interrogator
               has no information about the physical attributes of the subject, but only about
               its behavior. In the original version, this behavior is strictly verbal, but there is
               no reason in principle why it needs to be restricted in this way. The interroga-
               tor could askthe subject to draw pictures or even to carry out tasks in the real
               world, provided the visual feedbackthe interrogator received did not provide
               information about the physical appearance of the subject.
                 The same imitation game can be used for deciding about the appropriateness
               of any other cognitive description, including whether the subject is ‘‘conscious.’’
               Again, simply asking the subject whether it is conscious will not discriminate
               between themachine andaperson becausethe machinecan easily be pro-
               grammed to answer that question in the affirmative. Similarly, appropriate re-
               sponses to questions asking it to describe the nature of its visual experiences or
               pain experiences could certainly be programmed. But even if they could, would
               that necessarily mean that the computer would be conscious or only that it
               would actas ifitwere conscious?
                 If one grants that physical appearance should be irrelevant to whether
               something is conscious or not, Turing’s test seems to be a fair and objective
               procedure. Butitalsoseemsthatthere is afactatissuehererather thanjustan
               opinion—namely, whether the target object is actually conscious or merely sim-
               ulating consciousness—and Turing’s test should stand or fall on whether it
               gives the correct answer. The problem is that it is not clear that it will. As critics
               readily point out, it cannot distinguish between a conscious entity and one that
               only acts as if it were conscious—an automaton or a zombie. To assert that
               Turing’s test actually gives the correct answer to the factual question of con-
               sciousness, one must assume that it is impossible for something to act as if it is
               conscious without actually being so. This is a highly questionable assumption,
               although some have defended it (e.g., Dennett, 1991). If it is untrue, then pass-
               ing Turing’s test is not a sufficient condition for consciousness, because autom-
               atons can pass it without being conscious.
                 Turing’s test also runs into trouble as a necessary condition for conscious-
               ness. The relevant question here is whether something can be conscious and
               still fail Turing’s test. Although this might initially seem unlikely, consider a
               person who has an unusual medical condition that disables the use of all the
               muscles required for overt behavior yet keeps all other bodily functions intact,
               including all brain functions. This person would be unable to behave in any
               way yet would still be fully conscious when awake. Turing’s test thus runs
               afoul as a criterion for consciousness because behavior’s linkto consciousness
               can be broken under unlikely but easily imaginable circumstances.
                 We appear to be on the horns of a dilemma with respect to the criteria for
               consciousness. Phenomenological criteria are valid by definition but do not ap-
               pear to be scientific by the usual yardsticks. Behavioral criteria are scientific by
               definition but are not necessarily valid. The fact that scientists prefer to rely on
               respectable but possibly invalid behavioral methods brings to mind the street-
               light parable: A woman comes upon a man searching for something under a
               streetlight at night. The man explains that he has lost his keys, and they both
   16   17   18   19   20   21   22   23   24   25   26