Page 152 - On Not Speaking Chinese Living Between Asia and the West
P. 152

THE CURSE OF THE SMILE

        This book is written in the spirit of that ideal, but it also articulates a profound
        ambivalence towards it – an ambivalence which, I hope to show in this chapter, is
        both necessary and inevitable.
          To be sure, many critics have emphasized the fact that Australia remains a deeply
        racist society despite its apparent commitment to multiculturalism (and, for that
        matter, to reconciliation between indigenous and non-indigenous Australians).
        Indeed, it seems fair to say that an acceptance of the values of pluralism and
        tolerance does not guarantee a disappearance of racism (Hage 1994; Stratton
        1998). It is in recognition of this perceived incomplete abolition of the racist taint
        that the Labor government has initiated the adoption of racial vilification laws,
        for example. One problem with such avowedly ‘anti-racist’ measures (and the
        discourses that go along with them) is that they tend to be formulated from
        the implicit assumption that it is possible to make racism disappear. In this way,
        racism is tacitly conceived as deviant from the non-racist norm, an extremist
        aberration, something that, like a cancer, can be removed from the social body.
        What is constructed as a consequence is the image of a society which, in the end,
        will be free of racial prejudice and discrimination. But I want to argue that the
        idealized fantasy of such a purified, squeaky clean utopia only blinds us to the always
        less-than-perfect messiness of daily life in social space, where ‘cultural diversity’
        can have many different, complex and contradictory meanings and effects.
          The myth of pluralist tolerance (or tolerant pluralism) itself plays an important
        role in upholding such a fantasy. While Australians are now interpellated as being
        tolerant and as seeing tolerance as a virtue, the discourse of multiculturalism has
        by and large relegated intolerance to the realm of the forbidden, the ‘politically
        incorrect’. Stronger still, precisely because intolerance (except in exceptional
        cases) has been legislated against as violating the preferred, multicultural order, the
        expression of actual and real tensions resulting from living in a culturally diverse
        society – and the feelings of resentment and animosity they can induce – cannot
        be done without risking being branded as evidence of ‘racism’, and explained away
        in the process. In other words, as the case of Pauline Hanson has abundantly
        proven, the imaginary construction of ‘multicultural Australia’ depends on a
        demonization of the racist other. It is based on the assumption that when all
        intolerance has finally been purged, the non-racist, tolerant utopia will be realized.
          The problem with this representation lies in the simple binary oppositioning and
        separating out of (good) tolerance and (bad) intolerance, and in the illusion that
        we can have one without the other. It should be noted, however, that tolerance
        itself is irrevocably dependent on intolerance, insofar as it can only establish itself


        through a fundamental intolerance towards intolerance. As Slavoj Zizek has
        remarked:
            The traditional liberal opposition between ‘open’ pluralist societies and
            ‘closed’ nationalist-corporatist societies founded on the exclusion of the
            Other has thus to be brought to its point of self-reference: the liberal gaze
            itself functions according to the same logic, insofar as it is founded upon


                                       141
   147   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157