Page 68 - Privacy in a Cyber Age Policy and Practice
P. 68

EIGHT NAILS INTO KATZ’S COFFIN  53

             Much more important is the question of whether the courts should be
           guided by consensus even when it can be accurately determined. True,
           consensus has a prudential value. The courts should not stray too far from
           public consensus, lest they lose their legitimacy or stray into a bitter culture
           war of the kind that occurred around reproductive rights (i.e., decisional
           privacy). However, consensus has no standing from a normative viewpoint
           when rights are at stake. Thus, if an overwhelming majority of Americans
           agrees that women are second-class citizens or that “fishing expeditions” by
           the police are fully acceptable because “those who did nothing wrong have
           nothing to hide,” this does not mean that a court should accept this consen-
           sus and allow it to trump the court’s judgment as to what the Constitution
           entails and what is just and right. In short, from a normative viewpoint, the
           expectation of the public as to what and who may or may not be searched
           should matter little.
             Because this point is crucial, an elaboration follows. Katz runs rough-
           shod over the elementary but essential fact that the political system of the
           United States is not a simple democracy but a liberal democracy. (Others
           call it a republic; I would prefer the term constitutional democracy.) The
           essence of this regime is that it combines two very distinct principles. The
           first is majoritarianism: when we differ, we choose our course based on
           which position garners more votes. The other is liberalism: the Constitu-
           tion deliberately ensconces a set of rights, which makes them so difficult to
           amend that one should usually take them as a given. To put it differently,
           the majority can decide what it prefers as long as this preference does not
           entail violating anybody’s rights to speak freely, to worship, to assemble, to
           petition, and so on. The right to privacy is one of these rights. Therefore, if
           the courts were to decide whether or not a particular situation is covered
           by the right to privacy based on what the masses told a pollster or what
           the judges somehow determine the societal view to be—the courts would
           in effect turn a right, which is sacrosanct and etched in stone, into a mass-
           driven, pliable, ephemeral, ever-changing concept.
             Thus, Americans showed very little concern for privacy in the months
           that followed the 2001 attacks on the American homeland and much more
                                                                    25
           concern when no new major attacks took place over the next ten years.
           They are sure to change their collective mind one more time if another
           attack occurs. If one bases a constitutional right on such a foundation, one
           might as well tie it to a weather vane. In short, if Katz is allowed to stand
           and the courts continue to follow it, the result would be to reduce the right
           of privacy at best to a mere matter of democratic majority rule.
             I write “at best” because Katz is not more aligned with the democratic
           half of the United States regime than it is with the liberal/constitutional
           half. In deciding those public policy issues that are not covered by rights
   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73