Page 178 - Smart Thinking: Skills for Critical Understanding and Writing, 2nd Ed
P. 178

ANSWERS, DISCUSSION, AND FURTHER ADVICE 16 5

       Exercise 5.4

       a   An argument to support this claim would have to address the meaning of the
           word 'failed': Has communism failed communists or has it failed as a polit-
           ical and economic system? Does it mean failed of its own accord or defeated
           by the economic power of capitalism?
       b   The strongly descriptive nature of this claim probably means that using
           authorities is better than using supporting reasoning for such a claim.
       c   Although the Australian political system could be used as evidence, such an
           argument might not address the hidden implications that democracy here
           refers to the daily lives of Australia's citizens (freedom, choice, individuality)
           rather than the strict legal definition of the Australian political system.
       d   The extreme nature of this claim (relative to majority opinion) would suggest
           the need for a strong supporting argument that might explain the benefits to
           society (if any) of such a step.
       e   This is a descriptive claim; it would be better to leave it as self-evident in case
           our readers become incensed that we feel the need to convince them of some-
           thing so 'obvious'!
       f   We might recognise situations in which, even with a broken leg, immediate
           medical treatment is impossible or inappropriate. Any argument would have
           to take such considerations into account.
         Note my advice that claims b and f do not require argument but, instead,
       reference to authority. Deciding when not to reason directly for a claim is part
       of the smart thinker's bag of tricks. Generally speaking, these six claims need to
       be assessed, first of all, in relation to the events, situations, or decisions that they
       represent. Such an assessment is the traditional objective judgment of truth: if
       the 'objects' described or stated in the claim are truly represented, then the
       claims are acceptable. But, it is not enough to assess in this manner when
       thinking about communicating an argument or explanation. Reasoning is a
       social act, which requires us to think about the contexts in which we might
       provide arguments and explanations: what do others judge these claims to be?
       We must reason in ways that take account of the knowledge and assumptions of
       our audience, and also conform to the accepted conventions of the circum-
       stances in which we are arguing or explaining. For example, an audience of
       marijuana-smokers may well accept claim d without question; an audience of
       young people who have 'always' had television in their lives might need the
       support of some authority before accepting claim b; in an academic paper or
       essay, claim e, obvious though it may be, would need to be given some explana-
       tion and analysis; in a short discussion between paramedics at a motor vehicle
       crash, claim f would probably be stated without the need for argument in its
       favour. Finally, decisions about the extent to which we present claims as being
       self-evident depend on our conclusions. In any argument or explanation, it is
       the specific conclusion that can help us determine (given the inevitable limi-
       tations on available time or space for reasoning) what we explain in more detail
   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182   183