Page 85 - Smart Thinking: Skills for Critical Understanding and Writing, 2nd Ed
P. 85

72  SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING








                        ...©•©...







                      ©




          Claims that argue for or explain another claim are always placed above them;
       claims that work together to form one reason are placed alongside one another, as a
       chain of dependent premises. Getting the diagram right doesn't make this happen,
       it is a way of representing—in a structured format—what is happening in our
       minds.
          We tend to imagine that strong reasoning involves understanding and using a
       number of different reasons for our conclusion, giving our arguments and
       explanations intellectual breadth. This view has considerable merit (and we
       examine it in more detail in the next section), but it does not mean that we can
       ignore the requirement to argue and explain in depth. Learning to 'unpack' what we
       initially think of as a straightforward, simple reason and to express it as a number
       of distinct, but dependent, premises is the only way to make sure our reasoning is
       not too shallow.
          For example, in relation to higher education, deep reasoning will bring out the
       current debate about whether education is vocational (training for employment) or
       liberal (education for the individual's own life). It would engage with the complex
       issues of who pays, against a background of reduced government spending and
       increased personal wealth for some Australians. It would engage with the social
       purposes of education (education for individual benefit or for social improvement).
       Each of these issues is worthy of significant argument and explanation in its own
       right. Such an approach ensures that our reasoning addresses all the issues raised by
       the conclusion: the meaning of certain words, the values that we are seeking to
       express, the exact way in which certain situations come about, and so on.

       Avoiding implied premises

       If, in unpacking our reason and turning it into premises, we leave out a premise that
       should (analytically speaking) be there, then we have made a serious error. Such a
       claim would not be 'missing' exactly, but rather would be implied by the connection
       between the claims that are explicitly stated. That we do often 'leave out' some of
   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90