Page 41 - Aesthetic Formations Media, religion, and the Sense
P. 41

26                     Birgit Meyer

          to pay more attention to political aesthetics—understood in the broad sense
          advocated in Section II—so as to better understand how power works (see
          also Rancière 2006).
         7.  Taking inspiration from Michel Foucault and Judith Butler (1999) on the
          process of subjectivation through which modern subjects are formed,
          Mahmood closely examines the formative power of the Islamic piety move-
          ment in the making of embodied female religious subjectivities. In so doing,
          she moves beyond a dualistic understanding of religious regimes and individ-
          ual persons, and calls attention to the importance of formation in the double
          sense advocated here.
         8.  He states: “As long as it stays alive (that is, as long as it is being experienced),
          aesthetic community is shot through with a paradox: since it would betray or
          refute freedom of its members were it to claim non-negotiable credentials, it
          has to keep its entrances and exits wide open. But were it to advertise the
          resulting lack of binding power, it would fail to perform the reassuring role
          which for the faithful was their prime motive in joining in” (2001: 65).
         9.  “Aesthetic community” is the—rather misleading—English translation of
          Kant’s (2001 [1790]) notion of sensus communis aestheticus (aesthetischer Gemein-
          sinn in the German original). Kant presupposed the subjective universality of
          aesthetic experience and judgments of taste as solely based on feelings, not con-
          cepts. The sensus communis aestheticus does not refer to an actual community,
          but to a universal faculty to judge taste and experience beauty, the main point
          being that this faculty can be assumed to exist. Not only is this understanding
          grounded in the problematic limitation of aesthetics to beauty, it also separates
          concepts and feelings and locates the faculty of experiencing pleasure in a disin-
          terested beholder.
       10.  Perception, it needs to be noted, always involves a kind of concentration, fil-
          tering out what disturbs the intensity of a particular experience. Indeed, as
          Jojada Verrips argues (2006), aisthesis always implies some kind of anaesthesia.
          See also Crary (2001).
       11.  Obviously, this resonates with Bourdieu’s work on habitus, as an embodied
          disposition, and taste and style as modes of distinction.
       12.  Until recently, the study of visual culture was highly ocular-centric. However,
          in the past decade, even in the study of media that are closely associated with
          the eye—such as pictures, photographs, and films—scholars have been con-
          cerned with taking into account the interplay of the senses, and the visceral,
          affective dimension of visual culture (Sobchack 2004; Pinney 2004; Morgan

          1998, 2005, 2007; Mitchell 2005; Freedberg 1989; Howes 2003; Verrips
          2002).
       13.  I use “transcendental” with some hesitation and for lack of a better term, in
          the sense of a power that is framed to be beyond the ordinary and in this sense
          “other” or “alter” (see also Csordas 2004). I explain at some length in another
          publication that my understanding of the transcendental does not postulate
          the existence of a Numinous Power out there, but is grounded in the here and
          now, in that my interest lies in how religions induce experiences of the tran-
          scendental in the here and now (Meyer 2006a). I also opt for using the notion
   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45   46