Page 115 - Between One and Many The Art and Science of Public Speaking
P. 115

82                    Part 1  Foundations



                                        lies ineffective. Consider voting as another example. You might think you don’t
                                        need to vote because your own vote doesn’t make a difference. But imagine that
                                        as a universal rule: “Since individual votes don’t matter, voting is unnecessary.”
                                        If not voting were a universal rule, democracy would collapse. So Kant gives us
                                        a test for specifi c ethical rules. To be an ethical principle, a rule or maxim must
                                        be capable of being applied universally.
                                          One of the most important ethical rules that Kant proposed relates directly to
                                        the public speaker. Kant proposed the maxim “Act in such a way that you always
                                        treat humanity whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as
                                                                                6
                                        a means, but always at the same time as an end.”  One practical implication of this
                                        maxim is that speakers should treat audience members with respect, not sim-
                                        ply as a means of achieving their goals. Conversely, audience members should
                                        respect and treat speakers as fellow human beings, not as objects of derision.
                                        Obviously, then, tactics that deceive or demean either an audience or a speaker
                                        would be unacceptable.
                                          Kant’s categorical imperative is not without drawbacks. Consider truth tell-
                                        ing. If lying is unacceptable in any circumstance, innocent people may suffer
                                        as a consequence. Miep Gies, for example, lied to authorities throughout World
                                        War II to protect the Jews she was hiding from the Nazis, including a young girl
                                        named Anne Frank. But even us common folk sometimes tell “little white lies,”
                                        especially when they are intended to protect the feelings of others. Although we
                                        may be told as children, “honesty is the best policy,” we soon learn not to take
                                        the saying too literally. Thus, we choose to be less than brutally honest when
                                        asked to comment on a friend’s appearance or let our true feelings be known
                                        about the friend’s latest “love interest.” In short, even the most highly ethical
                                        among us are likely to occasionally tell something less than “the truth, the whole
                                        truth, and nothing but the truth.”
                                          Of course, one can reformulate Kant’s rule and say people shouldn’t lie except
                                        under certain circumstances, such as when necessary to save lives or prevent
                                        hurt feelings. But that creates another problem: How do we know which actions
                                        fall under these conditions? Rachels points out a key problem with Kant’s uni-
                                        versalism: “For any action a person might contemplate, it is possible to specify
                                        more than one rule that he or she would be following; some of these rules will be
                                        ‘universalizable’ and some will not. . . . For we can always get around any such
                                        rule by describing our action in such a way that it does not fall under that rule
                                        but instead comes under a different one.” 7


                                        Does the Good of the Many Outweigh
                                        the Good of the Few?

                                        Another ethical standard, utilitarianism, was proposed by English philosophers
                  utilitarianism
                                        Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and Henry Sidgwick.  Utilitarianism is
                  The philosophy based on
                                        based on the principle that the aim of any action should be to provide the great-
                  the principle that the aim
                                        est amount of happiness for the greatest number of people. These philosophers
                  of any action should be
                                        sought the greatest good for the greatest number. And they specifi cally defi ned
                  to provide the greatest
                  amount of happiness for   the good as that which creates happiness—“not the agent’s own greatest happi-
                  the greatest number of   ness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether.” 8
                  people.                 This certainly is a useful standard for the public speaker. Most topics on
                                        which you will speak are about choices and trade-offs. If we trim social spending
   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120