Page 33 - Cultural Studies of Science Education
P. 33

2  Nurturing Morally Defensible Environmentalism                 9

            the conservation of civil liberties, freedom, oral narratives, species and habitats, the
            arts, or conviviality, should not be limited by a politics of conservative and liberal.
            With few exceptions, both politics generate and regenerate forms of anthropocentric
            tendencies and consumerism as unquestioned platforms. Hence ecojustice does not
            represent  a  neoconservative  or  neoliberal  position  within  philosophy.  Ecojustice
            does not seek to renew a philosophical romanticism, which serves as a challenge
            for  scholars  who  strive  to  highlight  the  vulnerabilities  within  the  confluence  of
            ecojustice, place-based (science) education, and indigenous knowledge systems.
              For ecojustice educators, justice is fairness among humans, nonhumans, and the
            Earth.  Ecojustice  is  different  from  “social  justice”  and  “environmental  justice,”
            where only humans and animals have some defensible rights. Just because the soil
            is not easily defended, it does have the potential of defensible environmental rights,
            which may require advocates. In terms of ecojustice, responsibility for justice falls
            on  those  who  live  within  particular  communities,  where  justice  is  more  fully
            defined by law and rights. Justice then applies to becoming more informed, reading
            newspapers, articles and books, and granting the same status to learning from the
            literacies  of  those  who  may  be  considered  illiterate  and  uneducated.  Because
            humility is a significant part of this philosophy, we must acknowledge those things
            we may never know and learn, and we must be willing to protect cultural and communal
            differences  and  biodiversity,  as  a  philosophical  principle  of  “justice  embedded
            within social ecologies.” Dewey highlighted this transactional approach early in his
            work (1916/1966). He notes that subjects are learned and focused on evaluating the
            wider spectrum of societal problems in order to set things right. In order to do this,
            cultural  traditions  and  habits  are  endorsed  through  intergenerational  relations.
            These things help teachers and their students to evaluate the curriculum of the larger
            society and environment. Teachers and students share some of the responsibility for
            moving towards the common good, which can be interpreted as the basis for which
            degradation is mediated together. Justice is shared and mediated in common. When
            we say that we are mediated by just relations, it is to say that we ought to be compelled
            to do what is just. Although legal constraint is the most obvious aspect of justice in
            most societies there is also an underlying aspect of moral obligations. Thus, if we
            are  not  punished  by  the  law,  we  are  punished  by  the  punitive  opinion  of  other
            people, or the burden of bad conscience. In terms of ecojustice, there are few juries
            to enact judgment in the sense of moral reprisals against those who commit heinous
            acts of cultural and ecological violence.
              Justice implies something that is right to do, and wrong not to do, but also something
            which can be defensibly claimed from us to have moral rights. We should not
            be held responsive to the generosity of others who have insufficiently claimed to
            have developed a moralist ecology. A question of what these ecologies should provide
            for humans is not exempt from moral theory. Hopefully, this section will open the
            mind  to  some  possibilities  for  defending  ecological  rights  in  ecojustice  theory,
            beyond some human acquired debts to natural systems for which Nature is due. The
            “acquired debt” stance within environmental philosophy is a taken-for-granted sup-
            position that may need more conversation before these characteristics of ecojustice
            become convincing. Consider, for example, how “ruthless” Nature might be judged
   28   29   30   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38