Page 200 - Culture Media Language Working Papers in Cultural Studies
P. 200

THEORIES OF LANGUAGE AND SUBJECTIVITY 189

                               Derrida’s critique of Saussure
            A  similar critique  of Saussure has been made  by the contemporary French
            philosopher Jacques Derrida. In Speech and Phenomena he offers a thorough-
            going critique of the tradition of rationalist and logical theories of language
                                   12
            through a critique of Husserl.  In his essay ‘Differance’ in this volume and in Of
            Grammatology  he addresses himself directly to Saussure’s problematic of the
                        13
            sign. Derrida argues that Saussure is self-contradictory because, in spite of his
            principle of the arbitrary nature of  the sign,  he  remains attached  to  the
            nationalist, ‘logocentric’ tradition in Western  metaphysics, which  presupposes
            the a priori, fixed meaning of concepts. In this tradition language is intrinsically
            related to the self-consciousness of rationality. It is what allows the subject to
            present her/himself to  her/himself.  He argues that this entire rationalist
            discourse, which includes Saussure, is founded on the concept of language as
            speech—speech which comes from conscious, rational minds. His own radically
            different approach is founded on a reformulation of the object of linguistics.
              Derrida starts from the Saussurean distinction between language as speech and
            as writing: ‘Language and writing are two distinct systems of signs; the second
            exists for the sole purpose of representing the first. The linguistic object is not both
            the written and spoken form of words;  the spoken form alone constitutes the
            object.’  His main point is that Saussure’s theory of representation here
                  14
            contradicts his principle of  the arbitrary  nature  of the sign, since if this  is  a
            general principle, the relations between phonemes (minimum significant units of
            sound) and graphemes (minimum significant written elements) must themselves
            be  arbitrary. Thus there  can be no ‘phonetic writing’. Furthermore,  Derrida
            points out that Saussure  privileges  the phonic level, as constituting the ‘true’
            object of linguistics: in his theory the graphic level must always be secondary. In
            short, the phonic level is elevated to a transcendental position. It becomes the
            ‘transcendental signifier’ or concept, which writing exists solely to ‘represent’.
            Derrida makes clear connections between this incidence of ‘phonocentrism’ (the
            privileging of  the spoken word) and the ‘logocentrism’ (reliance  on  a priori
            transcendental meaning) of Saussure’s theory as a whole.
              Derrida’s argument is, of course, extremely complex, and we cannot do justice
            to it here.  We can only indicate briefly the theoretical value of his critique of
                    15
            Saussure and some of its potential limitations. Its value, for us, consists in what
            Derrida has  to say  about the concept  of ‘representation’  in general and the
            connections between this concept and Saussure’s logocentrism. The point which
            Derrida makes is that  the ‘logocentric’ perspective  requires a ‘naive
            representivist’ concept of writing. However, as Derrida points out, the very tone
            of the ‘logocentric’ discourse, in its desire to separate out the inner meaning from
            its external ‘clothing’, puts us on our guard:

              One already suspects that if writing is ‘image’ and exterior ‘figuration’,
              this ‘representation’ is not innocent. The outside bears with the inside a
   195   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205