Page 394 - Handbooks of Applied Linguistics Communication Competence Language and Communication Problems Practical Solutions
P. 394

372   Martin Reisigl


                          porary unequal, i.e. preferential treatment. For this purpose, distinctions on
                          “grounds” of the above-mentioned social features are legally justified.
                             “Structural discrimination” is considered to be a type of intersectional dis-
                          crimination (see Makkonen 2002: 14). It can take the form of “institutional dis-
                          crimination” and is frequently not deliberately produced, though it can some-
                          times be intentionally effectuated by a short-sighted policy or institutional
                          practice. It usually concerns members of groups in vulnerable social positions –
                          in many societies, for example, women – and is often rendered invisible by
                          naturalization and backgrounding. To give just one example taken from Cren-
                          shaw and referred to in Makkonen: “Structural discrimination” is actuated in
                          states with immigration laws that try to prevent marriage fraud and require an
                          immigrant to stay in the new state for several years and to remain “properly mar-
                          ried” before she or he can apply for a permanent status. This legal regulation has
                          the consequence that immigrant women who have married a national and be-
                          come a victim of domestic violence have either the option to divorce and get
                          subsequently deported or to suffer continuing violence (see Crenshaw 1991:
                          1247; Makkonen 2002: 15–16; see also Piller in this volume).
                             As the above explanations of the disciplinarily distinct concepts of “direct”
                          and “indirect” as well as “explicit” and “implicit” discrimination show, we have
                          to be aware of the problem that different disciplines and analytical approaches
                          only seemingly speak about the same things when they use the same words. This
                          problem has scarcely been recognized in the relevant literature on social dis-
                          crimination until now. Thus, it is explicated rather extensively in the present
                          chapter, without jumping to a one-sided terminological proposal. My overview
                          leads to at least four conclusions, which could be taken as a basis for further at-
                          tempts to elaborate conceptual distinctions which could possibly be interdisci-
                          plinarily valid: (1) Discrimination in the negative sense of the word represents
                          an infringement of principles of justice. (2) Discrimination can either be com-
                          mitted by unequal treatment, where equal treatment would be just, or by equal
                          treatment, where differentiation would be fair. (3) The distinction between “di-
                          rect” and “indirect” links up with the relationship between discriminators and
                          discriminated. (4) The distinction between “explicit” and “implicit” relates to
                          the way discrimination is semiotically realized.



                          4.     Concepts of “discourse” in approaches to verbal discrimination

                          The analytical focus of the following sections lies on verbal forms of discrimi-
                          nation. Whereas Graumann’s and Wintermantel’s (1989) as well as Wagner’s
                          (2001) approach to verbal discrimination are primarily “speech act” oriented and
                          therefore try to analyse “discriminating as speech acting” and to identify “dis-
                          criminatory speech acts” (see Graumann and Wintermantel 1989: 193–201), the
   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399