Page 38 - Contribution To Phenomenology
P. 38

REFLECTION     ON  THE CULTURAL      DISCIPLINES         31

              within  the  intentive  process seems  best  called awareness  and, as  intimated,
              includes  species  that  are  presentational  (perceiving,  remembering,
              expecting)  and  representational  (e.g.,  awareness  of  objects  as  depicted  on
              the  basis  of  the  perceiving  of  depictions).  If  the  awkwardness  be
              tolerated,  there  are  thus  modes  of  "awaring"  correlative  to  objects  that
              are,  in  general,  "awared." Specifically,  the  awared  needs  to  be  described,
              according to  the  case,  as  perceived,  as  remembered,  as  depicted, etc., just
              as  awareness  needs  to  be  specified  as  perceptual,  memorial,  etc.  In
              contrast with awareness  in  the  concrete  practice  or  process  there  are  also
              thetic  or positional strata,  which  include  the  doxic believing,  the  pathic  or
              axiotic  valuing,  and  the  praxic  willing  and,  correlatively,  objects  as
              believed  in,  valued,  and  willed,  all  of  which  have  also  been  referred  to
              in  previous  parts  of  the  present  essay.
                If  being  thus  descriptive  and  reflective  defines  what  it  is  to  be
             phenomenological,  something still  needs to be  said  about how phenomeno-
              logy can be philosophical.  This is necessary because  there  are  phenomeno-
              logical  tendencies,  intra-disciphnary  criticism  included, within  many  of  the
              cultural  sciences.^  It  is  here  proposed  that  phenomenology  is  philosophi-
              cal when  it seeks  not  merely  knowledge  in a  particular  region  but general
              and  ultimate  justification.  Justification  begins  the  move  toward  ultimacy
              when  it  goes  beyond  the  limits  of  all  individual  and  even  all  the  species
              of  discipline,  i.e.,  when  it  is  quite  general  in  scope.  Beyond  this,  a
              broadly  realistic  ultimate  justification  would  involve  the  grounding  of  all
              positions  in  the  widest  objective  context.  Alternatively,  an  ultimately
              transcendental  justification  would  involve  the  grounding  of  all  objects  in
              an  intersubjectivity  whose  insertion  in  the  world  has  provisionally  been
              suspended  to  avoid  absurdities.  These  strategies  evolved  in  Ancient  and
              Modern philosophy respectively  and both have been  pursued  in phenome-
              nology.  Whichever  is  pursued,  the  aim  is  clearly  philosophical.
                If  the  foregoing  is  sufficient  to  distinguish  the  phenomenology  that  is
              philosophical  from  scientific  phenomenology,  then  it  can  now  be  asked
              how,  in  general,  the  phenomenological  philosophy  of  the  cultural
              disciplines  approaches  its  subject  matter.  As  intimated,  cultural  matters
              can be  approached  in a  direct  fashion  and  with  the  highest  purposes, but,
              because  the  matters  approached  are  so  complex  and  confusing,  there  is
              great  danger  of  arbitrariness  and floundering in  that  case.  The  oblique



                   ^  E.g.,  Richard  L. Lanigan, The Human Science of Communicology (Pittsburgh:
              Duquesne  University  Press,  1992).
   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43