Page 58 - Contribution To Phenomenology
P. 58

PHENOMENOLOGY AND          THE CLINICAL EVENT           51

              Science  and  medicine  are  practices  in  this  sense.  Indeed,  precisely
              because  the  practitioner  experiences  the  field,  s/he  comes  to  recognize
              what  Maclntyre  terms  the  "goods"  internal  to  it  (its  "standards  of
              excellence"  or  ^Virtues")  ([19],  p.  175)  and  perhaps  even  periodically
              reflects  on  one  or  another  aspect  of  it.  On  the  basis  of  such  experien-
              ces  and  reflections,  one  can  (and  sometimes  must)  stop  and  think  about
              the  field  and  one's  involvement.
                To  reflect  in  this  sense  requires  a  specific  shift  of  focal  attention
              (epoch6)—away  from  actual  involvement  in  clinical  cases  for  their  own
              sake, to considering them as examples  of  the  practice—an  attentional shift
              that  needs  to  be  sustained  throughout  the  reflective  project  (reduction).
              To  stop  and  think  about  the  efforts  and  actions  specific  to  any  field  of
              practice  is,  on  the  basis  of  one's  own  practical  experiences,  to  become
              reflectively  attentive  to  its  inherent  "intention"  ([38],  pp.  125-141).  This
              complex  act  might  be  termed  a  sort  of  "practical  distantiation,"  or
              circumstantial  understanding.  It  is,  more  simply,  to  reflect  in  the
              specifically  phenomenological  sense.
                At  one  point  Husserl  observed  that  this  method  is  the  very  same  as
              that  which  "a  cautiously  shrewd  person  follows  in  practical  life  wherever
              it  is  seriously  important  for  him  to  *find  out  how  matters  actually  are'"
              ([12],  pp.  278-279).  Just  this  type  of  seriousness  is  quite  evident  in  every
              clinical  encounter,  where  patients  and  physicians  (and  others)  know  how
             vital  it  is  for  everyone  involved  to  know  and  understand what  they  face.
              To  the extent  that situational participants  seek  to  understand, they engage
              in  at  least  a  form  (perhaps  only  the  first  stages)  of  reflection—"stages,"
              for  they  rarely  go  further  into  philosophical  issues.  Moreover,  although
              their  reflections  are  (Husserl  might  have  noted)  only  the  "beginning" of
             wisdom,  it  is  "a  wisdom  we  can  never  do  without,  no  matter  how  deep
             we  go  with  our  theorizings"  ([12],  p.  279).

              C. Evidence
                Whatever  may  be  at  issue,  the  point  is  that  the  "seriously  shrewd"
             person  must  judge  and  decide  on  the  basis  of  sound  evidence—precisely
             because  the  issues  faced  are  vital.  To  apply  Husserl's  words,  the  patient
             no  less  than  the  physician  must  judge  "on  the  basis  of  a  giving  of  some-
             thing itself,  while  continually asking  what  can  be  actually  *seen' and  given
             faithful  expression"  ([12],  pp.  278-279).  Whether  one  has  practical  or
             theoretical  concerns  (a  patient  trying  to  understand  what's  going  on  and
             what  to  do,  or  a  physician  trying  to  interpret  diagnostic  tests),  to  seek
   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63