Page 63 - Contribution To Phenomenology
P. 63

56                    RICHARD    M. ZANER

              that,  or  for  my  own  judgment  about  the  anger?  How  is  this  at  all
              presented  or  experienced,  such  that  judgments  can  either  be  well-made
              or  not?  Clearly,  things  are  quite  complicated:  how  emotive  qualities  are
              experienced  and interpreted, ultimately  how other persons are  experienced
              in  such  situations.  Without going  much  further  into  these  issues  ([39],  pp.
              181-240),  it  is  still  possible  to  tease  out  some  interesting  matters.
                Consider  merely  one  of  the  themes  that  have  become  prominent  in
              this  methodical  process.  Every  concrete  instance  of  clinical  encounters
              displays  a  remarkable  array  of  "feelings"—strongly  expressed  wishes,
              wants,  desires,  aims,  purposes,  puzzlements,  etc.  These  "feelings"  are
              evoked,  most  often  by  the  patient's  condition;  in  the  mentioned  case,  it
              is  primarily  the  fetus's  condition  that  evokes  the  range  of  feelings  noted
              (but  also  the  couple's  and  their  physician's  responses).  The  feelings  are,
              moreover, directed to  the  developing  fetus's  present  condition  (diagnosis)
              and,  as  efforts  "to  do  something  about  it" are  suggested  (therapy),  these
              are  aimed  at  its  range  of  possible,  probable, or  likely  futures  (prognosis).
              Accordingly,  feelings  are  constituted  as  oriented  expressions  of  moral life.
              They  are,  that  is,  displayed concerns  that  orient  the  participants  about
              how  to  be  most  responsible  and  responsive  to  the  specific  persons
              involved—regarding  the  fetus,  how best,  if  at  all,  to  help  it  be  or  become
              **whole," "hale,"  or  'Veil"  to  whatever  extent  is  possible;  in  the  case  of
              the  mother  and  father,  how  best  to  help  them  understand  and  adjust  to
             the  likely  outcome  (whether  of  diagnosis,  intervention,  or  prognosis).
             Whatever  else  "feelings"  may  be,  thus,  their  clinical  presentation  is  the
             concrete,  practical  display  of moral  concerns  about  doing what  is  believed
             and  hoped   are  the  right,  good,  and  just  thing  for  the  persons
             involved—^within  the  constraints  imposed  by  the  patient's  particular
             condition,  biological  wherewithal,  values,  social  circumstances,  and
             available  medical  procedures  and  resources.
                Feelings  are  indices  of moral life more  generally.  They  are  not  simply
             overt  reports  about  a  person's  subjective  (and  presumably  inaccessible)
             life  at  the  moment.  They are  not something  Uke literal  "ex-pressions:" the
             "pressing-outward" of  what  is  thought  to  lie  essentially  "inside" as  purely
             private  and  available  only  to  the  one  whose  feelings  they  are.  As  evoked
             by,  directed  to,  and  aimed  at  the  specific  patient  within  her  present
             distress  and  possible  restored  futures,  such  feelings  are  the  experiencing
             person's  own  moral  orientations  toward  the  circumstances  and  decisions,
             choices  and  outcomes,  actually  confronted.  FeeUngs  are  thus  not  in  the
             least  "subjective,"  if  by  that  one  means  private  ([39],  pp.  48-66;  [43], pp.
   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68