Page 67 - Contribution To Phenomenology
P. 67

60                    RICHARD    M. ZANER

              should  be  done  about  it  [21]: among  the  available  options, what  decision
              leading  to  what  action  ought  to  be  reached  (including  the  respective
              aftermaths  each  carries  with  it).  This  is  shared  discourse  which  patient
              and  physician  pursue  together  in  search  of  what  the  impairment  means
              (and, at  some  point  perhaps,  ought  to  mean)  to  the  one  who  has  it  (and,
              for  the  clinical  ethicist,  for  those  who  profess  to  help),  with  the  longer-
              range  goal  of  enabling  patients  and  physicians  to fit  their  always-evolving
              narratives  into  the  broader  story  (and  history)  Schutz  terms  their
              respective  "Ufe-plans"  ([29,  I],  pp.  47-49,  134-154)  with  their  respective
              moral  frameworks.
                (3)  The  case  I've  been  considering  is  merely  one  among  many.  To
              consider  it,  not  for  its  own  sake,  but  as  an  example, is  to  practice  a
              specific  version  of  free-phantasy  variation:  practical  distantiation.  It  is  to
              leave  the  immediacy  of  clinical  work  and  to  enter  the  terrain  of
              philosophical  deliberation—^where,  among  other  issues,  the  concern  is  to
              delineate  what  such  actual  encounters  reveal  about  moral  life  in  clinical
              settings  (and,  possibly,  more  generally).  It  is,  if  you  will,  to  learn about
              moral life from  the clinical  circumstances  of  those who actually face these
             difficult  situations,


                           X.  Review:  The  Clinical  Event  as  Context

              In  these  encounters,  the  clinician  is  concerned  with  the  specific,  unique
              situation  itself:  physician  and  nurse  seek  to  help,  benefit,  cure,  perhaps
              only  comfort  the  patient  and  family  members;  the  patient  and  family
              want  to  get  better,  have  the  problems  resolved,  or  perhaps  begin  to
              grieve  appropriately.  The  cUnical  ethicist,  on  the  other  hand,  is  focused
              on  the  highly  individual  clinical  relationship  itself  (the  encounter  itself),
              for  its  own  sake  (if  you  will, practical distantiation  itself.  On  the  other
              hand,  the  ethicist  is  at  any  time  free  (beliebig)  to  shift  attention  so  as  to
              consider  any  encounter  as  an  example  ([10],  pp.  413,  422;  [12],  pp.  247-
              249),  where  one  then  seeks  what  is  "invariant"  through  inspection  of  a
              range  of  examples—if  you  will,  practical  distantiation.  Focused  reflection
              on  a  range  of  examples,  that  is,  leads  one  to  what  Husserl  terms  the
              then presented  "coincidence in conflict"—to  *Svhat is  common" throughout
              the  range  of  examples  by  means  of  "free-phantasy  variation."
                From   this  reflective  inquiry,  it  becomes  clear  that  every  clinical
              encounter has  certain  common contextual themes.  Each  is,  at  a  minimum,
              constituted  as  a  complex,  mutual  relationship  between  two  reflexive
   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72