Page 65 - Contribution To Phenomenology
P. 65

58                    RICHARD   M   ZANER

                     substituting  another  expressive  movement  in  place  of  the  particular
                     phenomenon  implied  by  his  experience  ([28],  pp.  260-261).


              Accordingly,  he  continues,  our  experiences  of  others  are  not  simply  of
              their  bodies  (not  even  in  special  situations  such  as  physical  exams),  nor
              just  their  "souls"  or  "selves*'—these  are  not  abstracted  from  each  other;
              rather,  we  experience  embodied  persons  ([33];  [39];  [43]):

                     What  we  perceive  are  integral  wholes,  whose  intuitive  [i.e.  perceptual]
                     content  is  not  immediately  resolved  in  terms  of  external  and  internal
                     perception  . . . .  The  primary  awareness,  in  ourselves,  in  animals  and
                     in  primitives,  invariably  consists  of  patterns  of  wholeness;  sensory
                     appearances  are  only  given  in  so  far  as  they  function  as  the  basis  of
                     these  patterns,  or  can  take  on  the  further  office  of  signifying  or
                     representing  such  wholes  (28],  pp.  261, 264).

                We   experience  others—the  woman,  her  husband,  the  physicians,
              etc.—as  integral wholes,  as  embodied  persons.  In  turn,  it  is  the  latter  that
              allows  us  to  "see  the  worry''  in  the  "furrowed  brows"  and  **wringing
              hands,"  not  to  mention  in  her  words  and  their  paralinguistic  features,  in
              her  physiognomic  expressions,  etc.  [3]—all  of  which  occur  in  the  actual
              context  and  setting  in  which  she  is  encountered  [39].
                Not  only  do  we  judge  about  "objective"  things,  but  also  hold  various
              beliefs  and  make  knowledgeable  judgments  about  a  wide  range  of  other
              things  too  often  regarded  as  merely  "subjective,"  including  the  emotions:
              remembering,  touching,  thinking  mathematically,  calculating,  liking,  being
              happy,  and  on  and  on  [35].  Judgments  about  these  must  also  be  based
              on  evidences,  for  otherwise  there  would  be  no  way  whatever  for  us  to
              make  sense  of  that  couple's  worry  or  anger,  or  that  physician's  mistaken
              interpretation.  We  experience  the  anger,  claim  to  know  about  it,  form
             judgments  about  a  wealth  of  affairs  (e.g.,  the  physician  claimed  they  were
              angry  and  that  this  was  directed  to  him),  and  do  so  on  the  basis  of  some
              mode(s)  of  awareness, alertness,  or  experience—^where  evidence,  however,
              requires  just  certain  of  these  modes,  as  they  are  the  ones  through  which
              the  affair  is  at  all  encountered  as  just  what  it  is  (as  "it  itself').


                                        IX.  Dialogue

              Talking  and  Ustening  to  situational  participants,  certain  matters  become
              especially  prominent and  need  emphasis.  (1)  In general,  phenomenological
   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70