Page 97 - Smart Thinking: Skills for Critical Understanding and Writing, 2nd Ed
P. 97

84   SMART THINKING: SKILLS FOR CRITICAL UNDERSTANDING & WRITING

       needed here? Well, to say simply that the economy benefits may be countered by
       an argument that there is no point in having a strong economy if the result is an
       impoverished culture. In such a situation, the conclusion may well not be accepted
       and our argument would be ineffective. Or, for example, if we were to fail to
       provide reason c, those people in our audience who would themselves argue for the
       primacy of international relations in determining economic, cultural, and defence
       conditions might not be convinced.
         As we might expect, for most claims there are arguments for and against; there
       are explanations from one angle and another. Whenever we reason, we are, by
       definition, setting up an opposition with possible counter-arguments. To give
       sufficient support to our own conclusion, we must give evidence that defeats, or at
       least casts doubt on, likely counter-arguments in advance of them actually being
       mounted against what we are proposing. For example, we know that one significant
       reason that opposes our conclusion that 'Australia's current rate of immigration is
       too low' is that 'social tensions will increase with increased immigration'. If we
       know in advance that such a counter-reason exists and we fail to address it, then we
       are making our reasoning less effective. First, we run the risk of appearing to have
       failed to understand all the relevant issues (and thus casting doubt on our overall
       competence). Second, we may find people unconvinced of our conclusion, even
       though they accept all of the positive reasons we give. The response of such people
       might be: 'Well, defence, politics, culture, and the economy will all improve, but
       that means nothing if the society that all those other things serve is falling apart'.
       That we disagree will not matter; the error we will have made is that our disagree-
       ment has not been included in the original argument we presented. So, in general
       terms, effective reasoning requires that we cover all the relevant issues involved in
       establishing or explaining our conclusion, whether they are positive or negative.  3
         We do need to consider whether or not our arguments and explanations meet
       objective criteria of strength. We need to consider whether they are well founded
       and strong regardless of what any particular audience thinks of them. However,
       because knowledge is never used or useful outside a social, non-objective context, 4
       we must also consider the audiences of our reasoning. Hence breadth of premises
       can best be understood in relation to the burden of proof. In essence, to meet our
       burden of proof, we must mainly meet the expectations of our audiences, but not
       simply 'give in' to what they want to hear.
          If an audience, for example, expects to see, in a discussion of contemporary
       European-Aboriginal relations, some consideration of the history of those
       relations, then we would be failing our audience if we did not offer it or did not,
       at least, dismiss the relevance of such a consideration. Which approach we would
       use, of course, depends on our views of the topic, but as a general rule, it is fair to
       say that our arguments must address (either positively or negatively) those aspects
       of a topic that we guess our audience is expecting to see covered in our reasoning.
       Furthermore, if the members of our audience have mixed backgrounds—with some
       being more convinced by and interested in economic arguments, others by histor-
       ical arguments, and a third group by purely moral or ethical arguments—then all
   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102