Page 159 - Critical Dialogues in Cultural Studies
P. 159

ON POSTMODERNISM AND ARTICULATION 147

            beings,  that  we  remain  in  nature.  What  he’s  talking  about  is  the
            elaborations  of  social  and  cultural  organization  which  complete  those
            natural  structures.  Our  genetic  constitution  is  extraordinarly  open-ended
            and is thus a necessary but not sufficient way of becoming human. What is
            happening,  historically,  is  the  massive  complexification  of  the  social,  the
            overdetermination of the natural by the social and cultural. So Nature can
            no  longer  stand  as  the  ultimate  guarantee  of  materialism.  Already  in  the
            nineteenth  century,  Marx  polemicized  against  that  kind  of  vulgar
            materialism but there was, and still is, a sense in which orthodox marxists
            think that something is ultimately only real when you can put your hands
            on it in Nature. We can’t be materialists in that way any longer. But I do
            think that we are still required to think about the way in which ideological/
            cultural/discursive practices continue to exist within the determining lines of
            force of material relations, and the expropriation of nature, which is a very
            different question. Material conditions are the necessary but not sufficient
            condition  of  all  historical  practice.  Of  course,  we  need  to  think  material
            conditions in their determinate discursive form, not as a fixed absolute. I
            think  the  discursive  position  is  often  in  danger  of  losing  its  reference  to
            material practice and historical conditions.
              Question:  There  seem  to  be  two  separate  questions  involved  in  your
            description of that slippage. One is how politically and historically specific
            the  analysis  is,  and  the  other  is  whether  opening  the  discursive  terrain
            necessarily  takes  you  into  reductionism.  Is  the  slippage  the  result  of
            excessive  abstraction  and  idealization  that  loses  touch  with  the  political
            and  historical  limits  on  the  ways  in  which  particular  discourses  can  be
            articulated to one another? If what is lost in making the social formation into
            an  open  field  of  discourse  is  a  particular  sense  of  historical  necessity,  of
            limits within which languages are juxtaposed with one another in a social
            formation, that is a much more limited kind of problem. One simple way
            of  posing  that  for  Laclau  and  Mouffe  might  be  to  say  that  their  position
            doesn’t  have  enough  of  a  political  inflection.  That’s  not  necessarily  the
            same  as  saying  that,  because  they’ve  opened  the  door  onto  thinking  of
            society  as  a  discursive  formation,  they  are  necessarily  pulled  into
            reductionism.
              SH:  I  do  not  think  that  opening  the  door  to  the  discursive  field
            necessarily takes you in that direction. It doesn’t take me there. So I would
            prefer your first formulation. In Politics and Ideology in Marxist Theory,
            Laclau contests the a priori insertion of classes, for instance, into marxist
            analysis  because  there  is  no  way  to  substantiate  such  a  philosophical  a
            priori.  Yet  he  does  reintroduce  class  as  an  historical  determinant.  Now  I
            find it very difficult to quarrel with that. I think the question of political
            inflection is a very real problem with a lot of people who have taken the
            full discursive route. But I don’t think I would advance that critique against
            Laclau  and  Mouffe.  The  new  book  is  quite  striking  in  that  it  does  try  to
   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164