Page 52 - Critical and Cultural Theory
P. 52

RHETORIC
     which  itself  is  simply  not  present'  (Derrida  1981:  26-7).  Fictional
     texts  may  actually  be  regarded  as  more  honest  renditions  of  the
     workings  of  language  than  supposedly  factual  ones  because  they
     resist  containment.  They  'operate breaches  or infractions'  (Derrida
     1981:  69)  which  remind  us  that  language  and  meaning  are  not
     restrainable  because  they  spill  incessantly  over  borders  and
     containers.
       The  slippage  of  meaning  is epitomized  by  the  concept  of  differ-
     ance.  This  refers  to  the  principle  of  'difference':  the  mechanism
     whereby,  as  proposed  by Saussure,  a  sign derives meaning from  its
     phonemic  difference  from  another  sign.  (Any  two  signs,  such  as
     'cat'  and  'rat',  differentiated  by  a  single  phoneme  constitute  a
     minimal  pair.) 7  But  differance  also  alludes to  the  idea  of  'deferral'.
     In  trying to  establish the  meaning  of  a  sign  on  the  basis  of  differ-
     ence,  argues  Derrida,  we cannot  limit  ourselves  to  minimal  pairs,
     for  a  sign  leads  not  to  one  other  sign  but  rather  to  legion  other
     signs ('cat'  is not  'rat',  but  also  not  'mat',  'sat',  'can',  'cad',  and so
     on).  Western  philosophy has  endeavoured  to  arrest  the  deferral of
     meaning  by  subordinating  the  unpredictable detours  of  language
     to  overarching ideas,  or  transcendental  signifieds,  such  as  'reality',
     'truth',  'self,  'presence', 'man', 'god',  etc.  The displacing  character
     of  language, typified  by  rhetoric, has  been  kept  at  bay  by  recourse
     to  a  universal concept,  or  Logos, meant  to  function  as  a  unifying
     centre.  Western  thought  is fundamentally logocentric. At  the  same
     time,  in  its determination to  differentiate  between  reliable  (suppo-
     sedly  non-rhetorical)  and  unreliable  (rhetorical)  forms  of
     discourse,  Western thought  has  fostered phonocentrism:  the  super-
     iority  of  speech  (phone}  over writing. In  his deconstructive analyses
     of Plato,  Rousseau,  Levi-Strauss and  others,  Derrida  has  indicated
     that  speech  has traditionally been  seen  as immediate, natural  and  a
     guarantee  of  presence,  and  writing  as  artificial,  ambiguous,  a  sign
     of  absence.  Yet,  the  features  that  characterize  writing  apply  to
     language  in  its  entirety. Writing  has  been  used  as  something  of  a
     scapegoat  to  conceal  the  ambiguity and  unreliablity of  any  form
     of  signification.
       Paul  de  Man  (1919-83)  pursues  a  related  argument.  Writing
     (especially  literature  broadly  conceived)  has  conventionally  been
     regarded  with  suspicion  because  of  its  association  with  rhetorical

     7
     >^~  These  ideas are  outlined  in Part  I, Chapter  2, The  Sign'.

                                 35
   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57