Page 112 - Cultural Studies Volume 11
P. 112

106 CULTURAL STUDIES

            social fabric are treated as if they were rooted in ‘cultural’ differences—in other
            words, attributed to meaning systems rather than the politics of inequality—the
            social vocabulary of culture is a hindrance rather than an aid to examining the
            relationship  between  the  political  and  material  conditions  as  they  operate  at
            local, national and global levels.
              Permit me to suggest, as a hypothesis for reflection, that within the academy,
            if  the  drive  for  transforming  curricula  to  reflect  cultural  diversity  has  been
            pushed  by  advocates  of  critical  pedagogy,  its  actual  formulation  and
            implementation  has  been  undertaken  by  proponents  of  liberalism.  The  liberal
            view of society is rooted in the premise that consensus and sameness are integral
            to  political  and  social  equilibrium.  The  apparent  harmony  of  this  perspective,
            however,  is  marred  by  its  dependency  on  assimilation  and  common
            denominators  which  seek  to  obscure  particularism  and  parochialism.  This
            attitude  has  provoked  critics  of  liberalism  who  point  to  its fundamental
            conservatism  which  they  denounce  as  hypocrisy.  For  example,  I  think
            philosopher  Yedullah  Kazmi,  who  has  written  on  the  limitations  of
            multiculturalism as a liberal palliative, is correct in censoring its accentuation of
            cohesion and tolerance (1994). Kazmi highlights the tendency to blame the Other
            for  non-conformity.  In  his  estimation,  liberalism  adopts  an  accusatory  stance
            towards  the  Other’s  refusal  to  accept  the  pre-established  ground  rules,  thus
            impeding  consensus  and  disrupting  cohesion.  The  transferral  of  blame  to  the
            Other—let’s  say  the  subordinate  group—for  non-compliance  relieves  liberals
            from acknowledging their own implication in foreclosing real dialogue.
              Political philosopher Seyla Benhabib draws on the insights of Hannah Arendt,
            the Jewish political theorist and refugee from Nazi Germany. Against a tradition
            of  universalism  which  masks  ethnocentrism,  Benhabib  proposes  a  model  of
            moral  conversation  whose  goal  is  the  process  of  dialogue,  conversation  and
            mutual  understanding,  not  consensus.  A  moral  conversation  instantiates  a
            reversal of perspectives; ‘that is, the willingness to reason from the other’s point
            of  view’  (Benhabib,  1992).  This  formulation—thinking  from  the  standpoint  of
            others—accentuates the egalitarian and potentially radical possibilities for public
            culture. As Benhabib reminds us, the modern public sphere no longer allows a
            distinction between ‘the social’ and ‘the political’ precisely because the struggle
            to make something public is intrinsically a struggle for recognition, inclusion and
            justice.  The  public  sphere,  then,  is  the  intersection  of  interaction,
                                                    27
            intercommunication and intercultural encounters.  Against this background, as
            Benhabib persuasively claims, ‘the self-centered perspective of the individual is
            constantly  challenged  by  the  multiplicity  and  diversity  of  perspectives  that
            constitute public life’ (Benhabib, 1992:141). In other words, the particularity and
            otherness of an individual can be known only through her self-definition which,
            in turn, requires that she have a voice.
              I  have  raised  the  critique  of  liberalism  to  redirect  attention  to  the  sharp
            contrast between inclusion and multivocality—in the first, inclusion, the Other is
            always  the  outsider,  the  one  who  is  always  already  defined  as  different  and
   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117