Page 177 - Cultural Theory and Popular Culture an Introduction
P. 177

CULT_C07.qxd  10/25/08  16:28  Page 161







                                                                                    Queer theory  161

                      generate and guarantee the binary gender system. Against this position, she argues that
                      biology is itself always already culturally gendered as ‘male’ and ‘female’, and, as such,
                      already guarantees a particular version of the feminine and the masculine. Therefore,
                      the distinction between sex and gender is not a distinction between nature and culture:
                      ‘the category of “sex” is itself a gendered category, fully politically invested, naturalized
                      but not natural’ (143). In other words, there is not a biological ‘truth’ at the heart of
                      gender; sex and gender are both cultural categories.
                        Furthermore, it is not just that ‘gender is not to culture as sex is to nature; gender is
                      also the discursive/cultural means by which “sexed nature” or “a natural sex” is pro-
                      duced and established as “prediscursive”, prior to culture, a politically neutral surface
                      on which culture acts. . . . [In this way,] the internal stability and binary frame for sex is
                      effectively secured . . . by casting the duality of sex in a prediscursive domain’ (11). As
                      Butler explains, ‘there is no reason to divide up human bodies into male and female
                      sexes except that such a division suits the economic needs of heterosexuality and lends
                      a naturalistic gloss to the institution of heterosexuality’ (143). Therefore, as she con-
                      tends, ‘one is not born a woman, one becomes one; but further, one is not born female,
                      one becomes female; but even more radically, one can if one chooses, become neither
                      female nor male, woman nor man’ (33).
                        According to Butler’s argument, gender is not the expression of biological sex, it is
                      performatively constructed in culture. In this way, ‘Gender is the repeated stylization of
                      the body, a set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory frame that congeal over
                      time to produce the appearance of substance, of a natural sort of being’ (43–4). In
                      other words, gender identities consist of the accumulation of what is outside (i.e. in
                      culture) in the belief that they are an expression of what is inside (i.e. in nature). As a
                      result ‘“persons” only become intelligible through becoming gendered in conformity
                      with recognizable standards of intelligibility’ (22). 34  Femininity and masculinity are
                      not expressions of ‘nature’, they are ‘cultural performances in which their “naturalness”
                      [is] constituted through discursively constrained performative acts . . . that create the
                      effect of the natural, the original, and the inevitable’ (xxviii–xxix).
                        Butler’s theory of performativity is a development of J.L. Austin’s (1962) theory of
                      performative language. Austin divides language into two types, constative and perform-
                      ative. Constative language is descriptive language. ‘The sky is blue’, is an example of
                      a  constative  statement.  Performative  language,  on  the  other  hand,  does  not  merely
                      describe what already exists, it brings something into being. ‘I now pronounce you hus-
                      band and wife’ is an obvious example; it does not describe something, it brings it into
                      existence; that is, when the words are spoken by an appropriate person, they transform
                      two single people into a married couple. Butler argues that gender works in much the
                      same way as performative language. As she explains, ‘there is no identity behind the
                      expressions of gender; that identity is performatively constituted by the very “expres-
                      sions” that are said to be its results’ (Butler, 1999: 33). One of the first performative
                      speech acts we all encounter is the pronouncement, ‘It’s a girl’ or ‘It’s a boy’. Each pro-
                      nouncement comes with rules and regulations, which we are expected to follow and
                      obey: ‘little boys do this, little girls don’t do that’, etc. Various discourses, including
                      those from parents, educational institutions, the media, will all combine to ensure our
   172   173   174   175   176   177   178   179   180   181   182