Page 159 - Cultural Studies of Science Education
P. 159

136                                                        B.D. Rowe

            Conclusion


            Rollin believes most scientists are not educated: “We do not educate scientists or
            physicians to be virtuous citizens, we train them in a technocratic way” (p. 31).
            Notice the distinction he makes between what it means to “educate” and what it
            means to “train.” Training is merely preparation and instruction, mechanistic and
            highly  controlled.  While  beneficial  for  mastering  a  specific  skill-set,  training  is
            antithetical to dialogue, to synthesis, to the interdisciplinary approach incumbent
            upon  ecojustice  educators  in  teaching  socioscientific  literacy.  Education,  on  the
            other hand, involves questioning, contextual analysis, discernment, and conversa-
            tion. It furnishes the conceptual and practical conditions that cultivate the faculties
            of  reason  and  imagination  for  a  deep  ethical  and  aesthetic  appreciation  for  the
              ecological – that is, the relational – elements of our world. Whether we believe
            bioengineering is immoral or not, we cannot stop it. That does not mean that we are
            utterly powerless. Our power is education. The hope for a more humane science lies
            in our appetite and adeptness to engage in science education with the holistic fashion
            that ecojustice – indeed, that human experience – calls for.

            Acknowledgments  I thank Bryan R. Warnick for his thoughtful comments on previous drafts of
            this response.



            References


            Cavalieri, P., & Singer, P. (1994). The great ape project: Equality beyond humanity. New York: St.
              Martin’s Press.
            Habermas, J. (1990). Moral consciousness and communicative action. Cambridge: MIT Press.
            Kant, I. (1785/1981). Grounding for the metaphysics of morals. Indianapolis: Hackett.
            Mueller, M. P. (2009). Educational reflections on the “ecological crisis”: Ecojustice, environmen-
              talism, and sustainability. Science & Education, 18, 1031–1056.
            Regan, T. (1983). The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.
            Rollin, B. (1995). The Frankenstein syndrome: Ethical and social issues in the genetic engineering
              of animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
            Rousseau, J. J. (1762/1979). Emile: or, on education. New York: Basic Books.
            Shannon, T. (2000). Made in whose image? Genetic engineering and Christian ethics. Amherst:
              Prometheus Books.
            Smith, K. R. (2003). Animal genetic manipulation: A utilitarian response. In S. J. Armstrong &
              R. G. Botzler (Eds.), The animal ethics reader (pp. 323–331). New York: Routledge.
            Troyer, J. (Ed.). (2003). The classical utilitarians: Bentham and Mill. Indianapolis: Hackett.
   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164