Page 156 - Cultural Studies of Science Education
P. 156

9  What’s Wrong with Genetic Engineering? Ethics, Socioscientific Issues, and Education  133

              Notice  how  our  discussion  has  led  us  back  to  consequential  ethics;  we  have
            reentered the realm of the “problematic aspects” and unintended effects of biotechnol-
            ogy. This breach into the consequentialist paradigm supports my larger argument
            (which I will get to soon) about the educational value of emphasizing both ethical
            theories. For now, I will continue to raise deontological questions not because I
            have the answers, but because they are fundamental to ask to cultivate the sociosci-
            entific reasoning that Mueller and Zeidler describe in their chapter. It is the ques-
            tions, I believe, that are of educational interest.



            Respect for (Human) Persons


            In general, nonconsequentialists build their ethic around the principle of the equal
            respect for persons and violating this principle is another potential rationale for the
            universal wrongness of bioengineering. The principle postulates that human beings
            have inherent moral worth because we are rational, responsible, and autonomous
            beings. As such, persons are to treat each other as moral agents, worthy of respect,
            as ends in themselves and never as means to an end (Kant 1785/1981). Let us now
            apply this principle to genetic manipulation.
              Similar to the principle of the inviolability of nature, this one too entails disputable
            overtones and requires some questioning of its basic assertions. What constitutes
            personhood? Are there degrees of personhood, or is there a line of demarcation that
            we can draw between “person” and “nonperson”? What does it mean to be a “rational”
            and “autonomous” being? Are human beings the only “persons?” Prior to the last
            30 years, the answers to these questions were fairly straightforward. However, as
            we better understand the mental, emotional, and social lives of other nonhuman
            species (especially of other great apes) traditional conceptions of personhood are
            increasingly being challenged. In fact, some applied ethicists and scientists ascribe
            personhood, or at least a certain degree of personhood, beyond humanity (Cavalieri
            and Singer 1994). But for the sake of space and argument, I will assume that the
            only persons are human beings.
              If geneticists are able to conjure up new species by varying the genomes of a
            plant, a mouse, or a pig, what is to stop them from doing the same with human
            beings? For many, this seems unethical, perhaps outright terrifying. The manufacturing
            of human beings in labs defies our sentiments about human dignity and challenges
            our unique moral place in the world. So how, then, do we conceptually assess this
            question of human genetic control? To begin, if humans were to become subjects of
            bioengineering – say, scientists began to clone humans – then this would amount to
            the violation of the equal respect for persons’ principle. Some theological scholars,
            for example, argue that technologies such as embryonic research and cloning “dep-
            ersonalize” the human individual by inventing or manufacturing merely “products,”
            not free and dignified human persons (Shannon 2000). Deontologically speaking, it
            is  irrelevant  whether  biogenetics  is  used  for  a  good  purpose  or  an  evil  purpose
   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161