Page 136 - Privacy in a Cyber Age Policy and Practice
P. 136

124  PRIVACY IN A CYBER AGE

           these claims can be neither maximized nor fully reconciled, as there is an
           inevitable tension among them. It follows that we must work out some balance
           among the conflicting claims rather than assuming that one will always trump
           the others. This chapter applies this approach to the balance between national
           security and individual rights, particularly the right to privacy, in the context
           of recent surveillance revelations. These include the U.S. government’s phone
           metadata surveillance, which collects information such as caller ID, times, and
           duration of U.S. phone calls, but not what was said,as well as the PRISM pro-
           gram, which collects the Internet communications of foreign nationals. 3
              In contrast to applying this balancing approach, libertarians, civil
           libertarians, and a fair number of contemporary liberals tend to emphasize
                                                                     4
           individual rights and autonomy over considerations of the common good.
           At the opposite end of the spectrum are authoritarian communitarians
                            5
           (mainly in East Asia ) who privilege the common good a priori and pay
                                                                   6
           mind to rights mainly to the extent that they serve the rulers’ aims.  In
           this sense, liberal communitarianism occupies the middle of the spectrum
           between libertarianism and authoritarianism, and draws mainly on social
           pressures rather than state coercion.
              The text of the Fourth Amendment provides a strong expression of the
           liberal communitarian philosophy. It states: “The right of the people to be
           secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable
           searches and seizures, shall not be violated.” By banning only unreasonable
           searches and seizures, it recognizes by extension that there are reasonable
           ones, namely those that serve the common good.
              Public intellectuals, elected officials, and segments of the media tend to
           adopt a one-sided advocacy position whereby they champion one of the
           two core values of society, arguing that some individual right—e.g., privacy
           or the right to freedom of speech or assembly—is being violated and that
           the laws or actions responsible should be halted. They often argue that “it is
           against the law, hence it is wrong,” or that the court ruling or law on which
           a particular surveillance program is based violates a core value, such as our
           right to privacy, and hence should be rejected. They do not ask whether
           the other core value, national security, might justify some scaling back of
           these rights, and do not recognize that the balance between the core values
           has often been recalibrated over the decades. To remind the reader, there
                                                      7
           was no federal right to privacy until the mid-1960s,  and until 1919 the
           Supreme Court failed to endorse a single legal claim that the government
           had violated the (now semi-sacred) right to free speech guaranteed by the
           First Amendment—and even then it did so only in a dissenting opinion. 8
              In contrast to the one-sidedness of advocates, the courts, which often
                                   9
           use the term “public interest”  rather than “the common good,” regularly
                              10
           weigh both core values.  In several cases, they concluded that the threat to
   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139   140   141