Page 202 - Critical Dialogues in Cultural Studies
P. 202

190 POSTMODERNISM AND THE ‘OTHER SIDE’

            issue of the unpresentable in a gesture which has to be incessantly forgotten
            and repeated. Using a term from psychoanalytic theory, Lyotard calls this
            process ‘anamnesis’: the reencounter with a trauma or former experience of
            intensity through a process of recollection, utterance and invocation which
            involves  not  so  much  a  recovery  of  the  original  experience  as  a
            recapitulation of it.
              What  might  at  first  seem  a  quite  arbitrary,  unnecessarily  abstruse  and
            idiosyncratic detour through eighteenth-century German idealist aesthetics
            actually  provides  Lyotard  with  an  opportunity  to  flesh  out  his  central
            objections  to  Habermas’s  attempts  to  defend  and  build  on  the  Enlight-
            enment  inheritance,  to  revive  what  Habermas  regards  as  the  prematurely
            arrested project of modernity.
              For Lyotard uses the notion of the sublime as a kind of metaphor for the
            absolute nature of those limitations placed on what can be said, seen, shown,
            presented,  demonstrated,  put  into  play,  put  into  practice,  and  Lyotard
            implies  that  each  encounter  with  the  sublime  in  art  provides  us  with  the
            single salutary lesson that complexity, difficulty, opacity are always there in
            the same place: beyond our grasp. The inference here in the insistence on
            the  palpability  of  human  limitation  is  politically  nuanced  at  those  points
            when Lyotard talks about the disastrous consequences which have flowed
            from all attempts to implement the ‘perfect (rational) system’ or to create
            the ‘perfect society’ during what he calls the ‘last two sanguinary centuries’
            (1986a:6).
              Habermas,  publicly  aligned  with  the  Frankfurt  tradition  which  he  is
            concerned both to revise and to revive, has emphasized the emancipatory
            and  utopian  dimensions  of  art  favouring  an  aesthetics  of  the  beautiful.
            From  this  position,  the  fact  that  the  harmonious  integration  of  formal
            elements  in  an  artwork  gives  us  pleasure  indicates  that  we  are  all  drawn
            ineluctably  by  some  internal  logos  (reason  reflexively  unfolding/folding
            back upon itself through the dispassionate contemplation of form), that we
            are, in other words, drawn towards the ideal resolution of conflict in the
            perfection  of  good  form.  Here  our  capacity  both  to  produce  and  to
            appreciate  the  beautiful  stands  as  a  kind  of  ‘promissory  note’  for  the
            eventual emancipation of humanity. Lyotard, on the other hand, in a move
            which  mirrors  the  deconstructive  strategies  exemplified  by  Derrida,  takes
            the  relatively  subordinate,  residual  term,  the  ‘sublime’  in  the  binary
            coupling upon which ‘modern’ (that is, Enlightenment) aesthetics is based
            (the beautiful—[the sublime] where the sublime functions as that-which-is-
            aesthetic-but-not-beautiful)  and  privileges  it  to  such  an  extent  that  the
            whole  edifice  of  Enlightenment  thought  and  achievement  is  (supposedly)
            threatened.  For  whereas  the  idea  of  the  beautiful  contains  within  it  the
            promise of an ideal, as yet unrealized community (to say ‘this is beautiful’
            is  to  assert  the  generalizability  of  aesthetic  judgements  and  hence  the
            possibility/ideal  of  consensus),  the  sublime  in  contrast,  atomizes  the
   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207