Page 129 - Contemporary Cultural Theory 3rd edition
P. 129

ContCultural Theory Text Pages  4/4/03  1:42 PM  Page 120





                                      Contemporary Cultural Theory



                   no doubt, because of their determined focus on classical Greek
                   and Roman antiquity, rather than on direct comparison between
                   it and modernity, and in part because the genealogy promised in
                   the first volume was abandoned in favour of a concentration on
                   the ‘games of truth’ through which men think their nature as
                   selves (Foucault, 1987, pp. 6–7). This renewed concern with
                   discourse, as distinct from practice, might well be read as a retreat
                   from genealogy into something closer to the early archaeology.
                      In these two volumes, Foucault succeeded in demonstrating
                   the radical difference of classical conceptions of self and sexual-
                   ity, not only in such relatively obvious matters as ‘homosexuality’
                   and ‘the love of boys’, but also in the more fundamental question
                   of the nature of ethical conduct itself. For the Greeks, he
                   concluded, sexual ethics were not so much a means of internal-
                   ising ‘general interdictions’ as of developing ‘an aesthetics of
                   existence, the purposeful art of freedom perceived as a power
                   game’ (pp. 252–3). The radically encultured character of human
                   sexuality clearly followed as a necessary corollary of the entire
                   analysis. By implication, at least, this called into question the
                   supposed naturalness of dominant contemporary sexual codes,
                   most obviously their heterosexism. Foucault’s implied sympathy
                   for the Greek ethic of self-regulated sexuality had an obvious
                   relevance to a subculture defined quite specifically in terms of its
                   sexuality. Written under the shadow of his own developing
                   sickness from  AIDS, there was also a terrible poignancy to
                   Foucault’s concern for the ‘care of the self’. Little wonder, then,
                   that he should have become a gay martyr (cf. Halperin, 1995). The
                   problem remains, however, that for most of us, whether gay or
                   straight, both subjectivity and right conduct are about a great deal
                   more than sex. Moreover, as Foucault had himself made clear,
                   Greek sexual ethics rested on a ‘harsh system of inequalities and
                   constraints’ for ‘women and slaves’ (Foucault, 1987, p. 253). This
                   ethic of self-mastery was made possible, then, only by the exclu-
                   sion of most of the population and of a whole range of human
                   conduct—work, for example—from ethical consideration. It is
                   difficult to avoid the observation that we owe these inclusions,
                   in part, to that same Enlightenment Foucault had so cordially
                   detested.

                                               120
   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   133   134