Page 23 - Critical and Cultural Theory
P. 23

LANGUAGE AND INTERPRETATION
    concern  is: what  is  the  relationship  between  a  statement  and  the
    state  of  affairs  that  it  describes?  Relatedly:  is a  sentence  for  which
    there  is  no  such  state  of  affairs  necessarily  meaningless?  The  two
    most  influential  positions  in  the  history  of  Western  Philosophy  of
    Language  are  realism  and  nominalism.  The  first  believes  in  the
    existence  of  universal concepts  in  a  realm  separate  from  material
    reality and  maintains that  the  universal properties  shared  by  parti-
    cular  things  are  abstract  and  unchanging.  The  second  rejects  the
    existence  of  transcendental  universals and  asserts  that  objects  and
    their  properties  are  just  names  and  that  everything  that  exists is
    particular.
      The  Greek  Sophists  (fifth  century  BC) were  among  the  first  to
    examine  the  relationships  which  need  to  exist  between  words  and
    things  if  language  is  to  convey  knowledge.  Gorgias,  one  of  their
    principal figures, speculated  that  when we give one another  words,
    that  is all we give one  another:  there  is no  direct  transfer  of  shared
    ideas  or  concepts  from  one  mind  to  another.  Even  if  there  were,
    there  would  always  be  a  disparity  between  ideas  and  the  ways  in
    which  these  are  used  and  interpreted  in particular contexts  and  by
    particular  individuals. In  the  Cratylus  (c.  390  BC),  Plato  sought  to
    counter  the  Sophists'  relativism,  by  arguing  that  although  the
    words  we use may  be  purely arbitrary  and  conventional,  concepts
    are  not:  they  are  a  matter  of  truth  or  falsehood.  It  is  therefore
    vital,  according  to  Plato,  to  arrive  at  ideal  names  conforming  to
    the  true  nature  of  reality.  This  coincides  with  an  otherworld  of
    immaterial  and  eternal  Ideas,  or  Pure  Forms,  that  transcend  the
    physical world. Only  a correctly structured  and  furnished  language
    is  capable  of  accessing  those  universal,  unchanging  abstractions
    and  thus  communicating  knowledge. 1  Aristotle  (384-322  BC), by
    contrast,  opted  for  a naturalistic  approach.  He argued  that univer-
    sal  principles  are  immanent  in  things,  and  can  be  discovered  by
    identifying  the  common  properties  of particular  objects.  Language
    must  be  able  to  grasp  and  articulate  those  universals. In  different
    ways,  both  the  Platonic  and  the  Aristotelian  models  were
    concerned  with  language's  ability  to  represent  objects  or  ideas.
    This  position  was drastically challenged  by the  Sceptic  philosopher
    Sextus  Empiricus  (c.  200  AD),  who  argued  that  words  can  neither

    1  IV  For  further  discussion  of Plato's  theories, see Part  III, Chapter  6, The  Simu-
    lacrum'.

                                 6
   18   19   20   21   22   23   24   25   26   27   28