Page 27 - Critical and Cultural Theory
P. 27

LANGUAGE AND INTERPRETATION
      Is  it  possible  to  draw  a  clear  line  between  factual  and  non-
    factual  language,  science  and  nonscience?  Logical  Positivism
    thought  that  it  was:  theories  are  legitimate if they can  be  classified
    as  scientific.  The  Tractatus  follows  this  approach  in  arguing  that
    philosophical statements are  nonscientific  and  therefore  unreliable.
    However,  it  also  states  that  this  does  not  imply  that  nonscience
    should  be  condemned  -  rather,  it  means  that  it  cannot  be
    adequately  articulated  through  language.  Wittgenstein  states:  'The
    whole  sense  of  the  book  might  be  summed  up  in  the  following
    words:  what  can  be  said  at  all  can  be  said  clearly,  and  what  we
    cannot  talk  about  we  must  pass  over  in  silence'  (Wittgenstein
     1975:  6.53).  This  leads  to  a  paradox:  truly  important  things  must
    remain  unsaid, yet one must  be able  to  convey their importance  by
    not  talking about  them.
      The  sayable  and  the  unsayable  also  impinge on  the  question  of
    the  self.  The  knowing  self  sees  the  world  but  cannot  see  itself
    seeing  it:  I  can  say  'I  see a  blue  tiger'  but  cannot  see the  T  that
    sees the  blue tiger. Analogously, when  I look  in  a mirror,  I can see
    my  eyes but  cannot  see the  T  that  sees them.  There  is no  I, ego or
    subject  able  to  confer  meaning  to  what  it  sees  and  thinks.  T  is a
    linguistic point  of reference, not  a personal  possession.
      Establishing the conditions for  the  existence of a precisely mean-
    ingful  language is an  arduous  task.  The  grammatical  correctness  of
    a  sentence  is no  reliable guarantee:  an  utterance  may  be  correctly
    shaped,  yet  illogical.  This  is  documented  in  How  To  Do  Things
     With  Words  by  J.  L.  Austin  (1911-60),  the  founder  of  Speech-Act
    Theory.  Austin  argues  that  in  order  to  be  meaningful,  sentences
    must  fulfil  certain  'happiness conditions':  they must  refer  to  some-
    thing/someone  that  really  exists,  must  be  honest  and  must  be
    consistent  (Austin  1962).  However,  these  conditions  are  not  guar-
    anteed  by  grammatical  correctness.  Properly  structured  sentences
    can  be  meaningless  if  they  fail  due  to  lack  of  reference  ('John's
    children  are  bald  but  John  has  no  children');  dishonesty  ('I  say
    "I'll  be  there"  but  have  no  intention  of  being  there');  or  inconsis-
                                                            4
    tency  ('I  say "I  welcome  you"  but  then  treat  you as an intruder') .
      In  the  Tractatus,  Wittgenstein seems  to  be saying that  meaning-
    ful  propositions  are  scientific  and  well-formed  and  that  meaning-

    4  •*" The  relationship  between  grammar  and  logic  is  also  addressed  in  Part  III,
    Chapter  3, 'Rhetoric'.

                                 10
   22   23   24   25   26   27   28   29   30   31   32