Page 39 - Key Words in Religion Media and Culture
P. 39

22  Birgit Meyer and Jojada Verrips

             eye alone, and finally abstract thinking and reasoning based in their turn
             on  these  representations.  Particularly  after  Descartes  presented  his  cogito
             ergo sum, expressing his sharp division between body and mind (cf. Meyer
             2003: 22), the aisthesis of Aristotle, the aisthetic way of knowing the world,
             the knowing through our body, rapidly lost ground in intellectual circles.
             Alexander  Gottlieb  Baumgarten’s  introduction  of  the  term  aesthetica  in
             the middle of the eighteenth century to designate the science of sensuous
             knowing  (scientia  cognitionis  sensitivae)  in  the  classical  sense  was  a
             milestone, but it did not denote a return to or lasting reestablishment of
             more balanced relations between aisthetic and rational knowing of the world
             (Baumgarten 1936). It may be that his qualification of the aesthetica as a
             science that concentrates on the facultates cogniscitivae inferiores (inferior
             or lower cognitive faculties, i.e., the sensorial ones) of human beings, instead
             of on their facultates cogniscitivae superiores (higher or superior cognitive
             faculties:  i.e.,  the  rational  or  logical  ones)  contributed  to  this  lopsided
             development.  Whatever  the  case,  it  is  a  pity  that  Baumgarten’s  touching
             plea to philosophers to pay serious attention to the importance of aisthetic
             knowing or sensorial impressions of the world did not get the response he
             expected (see Schweizer 1973: 108–9; cf. Plate 2005: 19–20). This was a
             pity, for after him a trajectory was set in which the Aristotelian heritage faded
             into the background in works on aesthetica, and movement was instigated
             in a very specific direction. Aesthetica gradually became a cerebral science of
             the beautiful and the philosophy of art.


             Kant’s legacy

             A major role in this one-sided and rather narrow-minded development was
             played  by  Immanuel  Kant.  Kant  was  familiar  with  Baumgarten’s  seminal
             treatises  on  the  relevance  of  taking  into  consideration  ways  of  knowing
             through the senses or the body alongside those connected with the faculty
             of reason or the mind, and he deemed the aesthetic judgment of an object
             to be based on a subjective feeling of pleasure (Lust) or reluctance (Unlust),
             which  was  the  result  of  an  unintended  confluence  of  imagination  and
             reason. Nevertheless, he ventured toward a rather rational approach to this
             experience, as from his perspective the feeling of Lust or Unlust was based
             on a (pure) judgment of taste or on reflection by a subject that disposes of
             both Sinnlichkeit und Verstand (Vernunft) (sensuality and reason [common
             sense]).  Characteristic  for  the  feeling  of  aesthetic  pleasure  or  displeasure
             (and the experience of beauty or ugliness) is (1) that it is not related to an
             interest or does not generate a specific desire, (2) that it pertains to a single
             object and never to a class of objects, (3) that it can be judged as having
             a “Zweckmässigkeit ohne Zweck” (appropriateness without purpose), and
   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44