Page 40 - Key Words in Religion Media and Culture
P. 40

Aesthetics  23

             (4) that it (unreasonably) requests approval by others (see Kant 2001). In
             connection with beauty, Kant also dealt with the aesthetic category of the
             sublime  (das  Erhabene):  something  observable  that  generates  amazement,
             anxiety, and awe and transcends the beautiful. It is these two categories that
             form the pillars of his philosophy on aesthetics.
               Though a host of other great thinkers, including Schiller, Schelling, Hegel,
             Schopenhauer, and Marx, to mention but a few, also dealt with aesthetics,
             it  was  Kant’s  approach  that  became  the  most  influential  for  decades  to
             come, especially among art historians and philosophers of art. In fact, it still
             informs, directly or indirectly, the work of many scholars studying beautiful
             objects and sublime phenomena. However, the acceptance of Kant’s cerebral
             and rational perspective on how experiences of the beautiful and the sublime
             could be understood implied a number of problematic divides through which
             aesthetics was framed as a rather limited field of inquiry.
               The  most  immediately  obvious  is  the  further  delineation  of  the  split
             between the realm of the senses or the body and that of reason or the mind,
             which  Baumgarten  so  ardently  wished  to  bridge.  This  implied  that  the
             senses and the body were of little or no relevance for the understanding
             of the sensorial and emotional impact of all kinds of imagery and objects,
             in the sphere of religion, for instance, on their beholders. We might call
             this process the de-sensualization or disembodiment of aesthetics (see Plate
             2005). The eye became a mind’s eye and the ear a mind’s ear, whereas the
             rest of the senses were numbed or an-aesthetized (see Buck-Morss 1992).
             Only with the rise of phenomenology, particularly as it was developed by
             Merleau-Ponty in his work on perception (1945), aisthetic experiences and
             knowing reappeared once again on centre stage. Merleau-Ponty’s Causeries
             (2002  [1948])  explicitly  dealt  with  such  experiences  in  connection  with
             the rise of modern art (see also Dufrenne 1973). Artists were aiming for
             representations of reality that were more in accordance with the fact that we
             do not perceive the world through our eyes alone but with all our senses:
             our entire body. It has been his work, among that of others, that has inspired
             many scholars from different disciplines in the second half of the twentieth
             century to design approaches that transcend the bodiless and dematerialized
             aesthetic theory in the philosophy of art.
               The second divide relates to the fact that neo-Kantian aesthetic theory
             was almost exclusively applied to what became known as high or modern art
             (i.e., art stored and exhibited in special places and spaces) and not to what
             was degradingly labeled as low art or kitsch: mass-produced imagery and
             objects meant to be consumed by vast numbers of people. In this connection,
             it is important to realize that this distinction between high art and low ran
             more or less parallel with a third divide that came into existence with the
             Enlightenment:  the  separation  of  the  artistic  from  the  religious  realm.
   35   36   37   38   39   40   41   42   43   44   45