Page 15 -
P. 15

4    MANAGING KNOWLEDGE WORK AND INNOVATION

                          is ‘possessed’ by individuals. Being able to make sense of the words and sen-
                          tences on this page is about knowledge. What an individual infers from informa-
                          tion is related to their cognitive capacity and interpretive schema, or ‘frames of
                          reference’, which they have acquired through life. It is reasonable, therefore, to
                          suggest that different people, with different past experiences, may infer different
                          things from the same information.
                            The ‘knowledge as possession’ view is implicit in much of what is written about
                          managing knowledge work within contemporary organizations. For example,
                          below we outline the very widely quoted work of Nonaka (1994), which talks
                          about how ‘tacit knowledge’ (the knowledge that individuals have based on
                          their personal experience that is hard to express or articulate) can be converted
                          into explicit knowledge (knowledge that can be ‘spelled out’ or written down),
                          which can then be communicated to others in the organization who will then
                          also ‘know’ without having to have had the same experiences. So, according to
                          this view, knowledge is something I possess and, like any of my possessions (say
                          a football), I can then pass on this knowledge (or football) to others.
                            This ‘knowledge as possession’ view has, however, been roundly attacked
                          by proponents of the ‘epistemology of practice’ (Brown and Duguid, 2001;
                          Gherardi, 2001; Lave and Wenger, 1991; Nicolini, Gherardi and Yanow, 2003;
                          Orlikowski, 2002). These writers start from the premise that ‘knowledge’ is
                          constructed and negotiated through social interaction. Knowledge is, therefore,
                          intrinsic to the localized social situations and practices (practices of saying things
                          as well as doing things) that people actually perform, and not something that can
                          stand outside those practices. Their studies show that social groups as diverse as
                          construction engineers, photocopier technicians, radiologists,  tailors, ship build-
                          ers and alcoholics do not learn to do things by converting tacit knowledge into
                          explicit knowledge which is transferred from one person to another but, rather,
                          by sharing and creating all kinds of norms, stories, representations, tools and sym-
                          bols which enable the experience of individuals to be related to the knowledge
                          of the wider community. Knowledge is, in effect, ‘enacted’ through the practices
                          of different groups and inextricably bound up with the way these groups work
                          together and develop shared identities and shared beliefs. For example, chefs
                          have access to recipes that hold explicit  written information on what ingredi-
                          ents to use and how to put them together. However, as any good chef will tell
                          you, they do not learn from this, as much as from the actual  practice of being
                          an apprentice with a Master Chef within a particular kitchen and social setting
                          that reinforces certain kinds of norms,  values and practices. It is this practice that
                          allows them to interpret and apply the recipes effectively and innovatively.
                            By taking these criticisms on board we can begin to see that the often used
                          saying that knowledge is a person’s ‘justified true belief’ – which dates back to
                          Plato and underpins theories such as Nonaka’s – is actually quite problematic
                          (Gourlay, 2006). This is because there are likely to be many possible ‘truths’
                          and, so, ‘truth’ (or what counts as truth) results as much from the negotia-
                          tions amongst social actors (and the tools at their disposal) as it does from any
                            personally held justifications. What finally comes to be accepted as ‘true’ is often









                                                                                             6/5/09   6:56:37 AM
                  9780230_522015_02_cha01.indd   4
                  9780230_522015_02_cha01.indd   4                                           6/5/09   6:56:37 AM
   10   11   12   13   14   15   16   17   18   19   20