Page 233 - Communication and the Evolution of Society
P. 233

210                        Notes

         Whereas  in  systematically  distorted  communication  at  least  one  of  the
         participants  deceives  himself  about  the  fact  that  the  basis  of  consensual
         action  is  only  apparently  being  maintained,  the  manipulator  deceives  at
         least  one  of  the  other  participants  about  his  own  strategic  attitude,  in
         which  he  delzberately  behaves  in  a  pseudoconsensual  manner.
           3.  K.-O.  Apel,  “Sprechakttheorie  und  transzendentale  Sprachpragmatik
         —zur  Frage  ethischer  Normen,”  in  K.-O.  Apel,  ed.,  Sprachpragmatik  und
         Philosophie  (Frankfurt,  1976),  pp.  10-173.
           4.  In  the  framework  of  Southwest  German  Neo-Kantianism,  Emil
         Lask  earlier  reconstructed  the  concept  of  “transsubjective  validity’”—
         in  connection  with  the  meaning  of  linguistic  expressions,  the  truth  of
         statements,  and  the  beauty  of  works  of  art—as  worthiness  to  be  recog-
         nized.  Lask’s  philosophy  of  validity  combines  motifs  from  Lotze,  Bolzano,
         Husserl,  and,  naturally,  Rickert.  “Genuine  value  is  worthiness  to  be  rec-
         ognized,  recognition-value,  that  which  deserves  submission,  that  to  which
         it  is  due,  thus  that  which  demands  or  requires  it.  To  be  valid  is  value,
         demand,  norm....  All  such  terms  as  ‘worthiness,’  ‘deserve,’  ‘be  due,’
         ‘demand’  are  correlative  concepts;  they  point  to  a  subjective  behavior  cor-
         responding  to  validity—worthy  to  be  treated  or  regarded  in  a  certain  way,
         it  demands  a  certain  behavior.’”’  E.  Lask,  “Zum  System  der  Logik,”  Ges.
         Schriften,  vol.  3  (Tubingen,  1924),  p.  92.
           5.  Y.  Bar-Hillel  fails  to  appreciate  this  in  his  critique:  “On  Habermas’
         Hermeneutic  Philosophy  of  Language,”  Synthese  26  (1973) :1-12.  His
         critique  is  based  on  a  paper  I  characterized  as  provisional:  ‘“Vorbereitende
         Bemerkungen  zu  einer  Theorie  der  kommunikativen  Kompetenz,”  in  J.
         Habermas  and  N.  Luhmann,  Theorie  der  Gesellschaft  oder  Sozialtech-
         nologie  (Frankfurt,  1971),  pp.  101-141.  Bar-Hillel  has,  I  feel,  misunder-
         stood  me  on  so  many  points  that  it  would  not  be  fruitful  to  reply  in  de-
         tail.  I  only  hope  that  in  the  present  sketch  I  can  make  my  (still  strongly
         programmatic)  approach  clear  even  to  readers  who  are  aggressively  in-
         clined  and  hermeneutically  not  especially  open.
           6.  E.g.,  K.-O.  Apel,  Transformation  der  Philosophie,  vol.  2  (Frankfurt,
         1971),  pp.  406  ff.,  and  “Programmatische  Bemerkungen  zur  Idee  einer
         transzendentalen  Sprachpragmatik,”  in  Annales  Universitatis  Tukuensis
         Sarja,  Series  B,  Osa  Tom  126  (Tuku,  1973),  pp.  11-35.
           7.  Charles  Morris,  “Foundations  of  the  Theory  of  Signs,”  in  Excyclo-
         pedia  of  Unified  Science  vol.  1,  no.  2  (Chicago,  1938),  and  Signs,  Lan-
         guage,  Behavior  (New  York,  1955).
           8.  Cf.  my  remarks  on  Morris  in  Zur  Logik  der  Sozialwissenschaften
         (Frankfurt,  1970),  pp.  150  ff.
           9.  Bar-Hillel,  ‘“Indexical  Expressions,”  in  Aspects  of  Language  (Jerusa-
         lem,  1970),  pp.  69-88,  and  “Semantics  and  Communication,”  in  H.  Heid-
         tich,  Semantics  and  Communication  (Amsterdam,  1974),  pp.  1-36.  Tak-
         ing  Bar-Hillel  as  his  point  of  departure,  A.  Kasher  has  proposed  a  formal
         representation  embedding  linguistic  expressions  in  extralinguistic  contexts.
   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238