Page 238 - Communication and the Evolution of Society
P. 238

215                        Notes

         Harman,  eds.,  Semantics  of  Natural  Language  (Dordrecht,  1972).  H.
         Schnelle,  Sprachphilosophie  und  Linguistik  (Hamburg,  1973)  is  also  typ-
         ical  of  methodological  behaviorism  in  linguistics.
           58.  J.  L.  Austin,  How  to  do  Things  with  Words  (Oxford,  1962);  cf.
         the  bibliography  on  the  theory  of  speech  acts  compiled  by  E.  von  Savigny
         for  the  German  edition  of  this  work  (Stuttgart,  1972),  pp.  204-209.  J.  L.
         Austin,  ““Performative  Utterances,”  in  Philosophical  Papers  (Oxford,
         1970),  Ppp.  233-252,  and  ‘Performative-Constative,”  in  C.  E.  Caton,  ed.,
         Philosophy  and  Ordinary  Language  (Urbana,  Ill.,  1963),  pp.  22-33.  Ad-
         ditional  Austin  bibliography  can  be  found  in  von  Savigny,  Die  Philoso-
         phie  der  normalen  Sprache,  pp.  162-166.
           See  also  J.  R.  Searle:  “What  is  a  Speech  Act?,”  in  M.  Black,  ed.,  PAi-
         losophy  in  America  (Ithaca,  1965),  pp.  221-239,  reprinted  in  Rosenberg
         and  Travis,  eds.,  Readings  in  the  Philosophy  of  Language  (Englewood
         Cliffs,  N.J.,  1971),  pp.  614-628;  “Austin  on  Locutionary  and  Ilocution-
         ary  Acts,”  Philosophical  Review  77  (1968)  :405-424,  reprinted  in  ibid.,
         pp.  262-275;  Speech  Acts  (London,  1969);  and  “Linguistik  und  Sprach-
         philosophie,”  in  Bartsch  and  Vennemann,  Linguistik  und  Nachbarwissen-
         Schaften,  pp.  111-126.
           Other  sources  include:  W.  P.  Alston,  Philosophy  of  Language,  and
         “Linguistic  Acts,”  American  Philosophical  Quarterly  1(1964):138-146;
         L.  J.  Cohen,  “Do  Ilocutionary  Forces  Exist?,”’  Philosophical  Quarterly  14
         (1964)  :118-137,  reprinted  in  Rosenberg  and  Travis,  Readings,  pp.  580—
         598,  and  “Speech  Acs,”  Current  Trends  in  Linguistics  12  (1970);  R.  M.
         Hare,  “Meaning  and  Speech  Acts,”  Philosophical  Review  79  (1970)  :3-24,
         and  “Austin’s  Distinction  between  Locutionary  and  Illocutionary  Acts,”
         in  Hare,  Practical  Inferences  (London,  1972);  D.  Holdcroft,  ‘‘Performa-
         tives  and  Statements,’  Mind  83  (1974):1-18;  P.  F.  Strawson,  “Intention
         and  Convention  in  Speech  Acts,”  Philosophical  Review  73  (1964) :439-
         460,  reprinted  in  Rosenberg  and  Travis,  Readings,  pp.  599-613;  S.  Thau,
         “The  Distinction  between  Ebetic  and  Ilocutionary  Acts,”  Azalyszs  32
         (1972/73 ):177~183;  C.  Travis,  “A  Generative  Theory  of  Speech  Acts,”
         in  Rosenberg  and  Travis,  Readings,  pp.  629-644;  G.  J.  Warnock,  “Hare
         on  Meaning  and  Speech  Acts,’  Philosophical  Review  80  (1971)  :80-84;
         Wunderlich,  Grundlagen  der  Linguistik,  pp.  309-352.
           59.  Chomsky,  Aspects  of  the  Theory  of  Syntax,  pp.  3  ff.
           6o.  These  qualifications  are  stated  below  in  the  discussion  of  Searle’s
         principle  of  expressibility.
           61.  P.  F.  Strawson,  Individuals  (London,  1959);  M.  Dummet,  Frege,
         Philosophy  of  Language  (London,  1973);  E.  Tugendhat,  Vorlesungen
         zur  Einfuibrung  in  die  sprachanalytische  Philosophie  (Frankfurt,  1976).
           62.  On  the  analysis  of  intentionality  and  the  expression  of  intentions,
         cf.  W.  Sellars,  “Empiricism  and  the  Philosophy  of  Mind,”  in  Metaphysics
         (London,  1968);  W.  Sellars  and  R.  Chisholm,  “‘Intentionality  and  the
         Mental,”  in  Minnesota  Studies,  vol.  1  (1963),  pp.  507-539;  Sellars,  Scz-
   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243