Page 85 - Communication and the Evolution of Society
P. 85

62                         Communication  and  Evolution  of  Society

         the  following  two  statements  must  hold:  (a)  a  statement  to  the
         effect  that  certain  contexts  obtain,  indeed  those  required  by  the
         type  in  question;  and  (b)  a  statement  to  the  effect  that  speaker
         and  hearer  suppose  these  contexts  to  obtain.  The  spec#fic  presup-
         position  of  speaker  engagement,  on  the  other  hand,  should  not
         be  analyzed  in  the  same  way,  that  is,  so  as  to  yield  the  following
         two  statements:  (a)  a  statement  to  the  effect  that  there  is  a  cer-
         tain  engagement  on  the  part  of  the  speaker;  and  (b)  a  statement
         to  the  effect  that  the  hearer  supposes  this  speaker  engagement  to
         obtain.  One  could  choose  this  strategy  of  analysis;  but  I  regard  it
         as  unsuitable.  It  would  suggest  that  we  speak  of  the  existence  of
         an  engagement  in  the  same  sense  as  we  speak  of  the  existence
         of  restricted  contexts.  I  can  ascertain  in  an  appropriate  manner,
         through  observation  or  questioning,  whether  or  not  conditions  of
         generalized  contexts  obtain;  on  the  other  hand,  I  can  only  test
         whether  a  speaker  engages  himself  in  a  specific  way  and  com-
         mits  himself  to  certain  consequences  for  action;  I  can  ascertain
         at  best  whether  there  are  sufficient  indicators  for  the  conjecture
         that  the  offer  would  withstand  testing.
           The  bond  into  which  the  speaker  is  willing  to  enter  with  the
         performance  of  an  illocutionary  act  means  a  guarantee  that,  in
         consequence  of  his  utterance,  he  will  fulfill  certain  conditions—
         for  example,  regard  a  question  as  settled  when  a  satisfactory  an-
         swer  is  given;  drop  an  assertion  when  it  proves  to  be  false;  follow
         his  own  advice  when  he  finds  himself  in  the  same  situation  as  the
         hearer;  stress  a  request  when  it  is  not  complied  with;  act  in  ac-
         cordance  with  an  intention  disclosed  by  avowal,  and  so  on.  Thus
         the  illocutionary  force  of  an  acceptable  speech  act  consists  in  the
         fact  that  it  can  move  a  hearer  to  rely  on  the  speech-act-typical
         commitments  of  the  speaker.  But  if  illocutionary  force  has  more
         than  a  suggestive  influence,  what  can  motivate  the  hearer  to  base
         his  action  on  the  premise  that  the  speaker  seriously  intends  the
         engagement  he  indicates?  When  it  is  a  question  of  institutionally
         bound  speech  actions,  he  can  perhaps  rely  on  the  binding  force
         of  an  established  norm  of  action.  In  the  case  of  institutionally
         unbound  speech  acts,  however,  illocutionary  force  cannot  be
         traced  back  directly  to  the  binding  force  of  the  normative  context.
         The  illocutionary  force  with  which  the  speaker,  in  carrying  out
   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90